Pro-definability of spaces of definable types

By Pablo Cubides Kovacsics and Jinhe Ye

Abstract

We show pro-definability of spaces of definable types in various classical complete first order theories, including complete o-minimal theories, Presburger arithmetic, -adically closed fields, real closed and algebraically closed valued fields and closed ordered differential fields. Furthermore, we prove pro-definability of other distinguished subspaces, some of which have an interesting geometric interpretation.

Our general strategy consists of showing that definable types are uniformly definable, a property which implies pro-definability using an argument due to E. Hrushovski and F. Loeser. Uniform definability of definable types is finally achieved by studying classes of stably embedded pairs.

1. Introduction

In Reference 13, building on the model theory of algebraically closed valued fields (), E. Hrushovski and F. Loeser developed a theory which provides a model-theoretic account of the Berkovich analytification of algebraic varieties. Most notably, they obtained results concerning the homotopy type of quasi-projective varieties which were only known under strong algebro-geometric hypothesis on by results in Reference 1.

One of the difficulties to study Berkovich spaces from a model-theoretic point of view is that such spaces do not seem to generally have (in ) the structure of a definable set –where usual model-theoretic techniques can be applied– but rather canonically the structure of a space of types. Part of the novelty of Hrushovski-Loeser’s work lies on the fact that their spaces can be equipped with the structure of a (strict) pro-definable set, which granted them back the use of different classical model-theoretic tools. It is thus tempting to ask if such a structural result holds for other distinguished subsets of definable types and even for other first-order theories. It turned out this question is closely related to classical topics in model theory such as the model theory of pairs and uniform definability of types. In this article we give a positive answer in various contexts. Formally, we obtain the following result

Main Theorem 1 (Theorem 6.4).

Let be one of the following theories: a complete o-minimal theory; Presburger arithmetic; the theory of a finite extension of ; the theory of real closed valued fields ; a completion of the theory of algebraically closed valued fields ; the theory of closed ordered differential fields . Then, definable types over models of are uniformly definable. In particular, for every model of and every -definable set , the space of -definable types concentrating on is pro-definable in .

The fact that pro-definability follows from uniform definability of types goes back to an argument of E. Hrushovski and F. Loeser in Reference 13 which we present in Proposition 4.1. In return, uniform definability of types is obtained from the following criterion which relates it to stably embedded pairs of models of .

Main Theorem 2 (Corollary 6.2).

Let be an -theory such that

the class of stably embedded pairs of models of is elementary in the language of pairs;

for every small model and every definable type , there is a stably embedded pair such that is realized in .

Then has uniform definability of types.

Ensuring point for the above-listed theories makes use of characterizations of definable types à la Marker-Steinhorn. In the case of and , we prove such a characterization (Theorem 5.9) in the spirit of Reference 6.

As a corollary we also obtain pro-definability of some distinguished subspaces of the space of definable types which have a geometric interpretation. In particular, we aim to show that there are spaces of definable types in that can mimic Huber’s analytification of an algebraic variety in a similar way the space of generically stable types mimics its Berkovich analytification. We hope this can serve as a basis towards a model theory of adic spaces. In the same spirit, working in , there are spaces of definable types which can be seen as the model-theoretic counterpart of the analytification of semi-algebraic sets as recently defined by P. Jell, C. Scheiderer and J. Yu in Reference 14. This article aims to lay down a foundation for a model-theoretic study of such spaces. In a sequel, we will further explore structural properties of some of these spaces.

A natural question to ask is if such spaces are also strict pro-definable (i.e., pro-definable with surjective transition maps). Obtaining strictness is much more subtle and is often related to completions of theories of stably embedded pairs. Results towards a positive answer to this question will also be addressed in subsequent work.

2. Preliminaries and notation

2.1. Model theoretic background

Let be a first order language (possibly multi-sorted) and be a complete -theory. The sorts of are denoted by bold letters . Given a variable , we let denote the sort where ranges. If is a model of and be a sort of , we let denote the set of elements of which are of sort . Given an ordered tuple of variables (possibly infinite), we extend this notation and set

Let be a subset of (i.e. the union of all , a -sort). The language is the language together with constant symbols for every element in . Given an -definable subset , we say that a type concentrates on if contains a formula defining . We denote by the subset of consisting of those types concentrating on . For a -definable function the pushforward of is the function sending to .

We let be a monster model of . As usual, a set is said to be small if it is of cardinality smaller than . A type is a global type if . Following Shelah’s terminology, a subset is --definable if there is a small collection of -formulas (where only finitely many occur in each formula) such that .

We let and denote the usual definable and algebraic closure model-theoretic operators. Given a tuple of variables of length , a -definable set and a subset of , we let .

2.2. Definable types

We will mainly study definable types over models of . Recall that given a subset , a type is -definable (or definable over ) if for every -formula there is an -formula such that for every

The map is called a scheme of definition for , and the formula is called a -definition for . We say is definable if it is -definable. Given any set containing , we use to denote the type , where is any model of containing . We refer the reader to Reference 18, Section 1 for proofs and details of these facts. The following is folklore.

Lemma 2.1.

If is definable and , then is definable.

Let be a partitioned formula. A formula is a uniform definition for (in ) if for every model of and every definable type there is such that is a -definition for . We say has uniform definability of types if every partitioned -formula has a uniform definition, which we write . The following is a routine coding exercise.

Lemma 2.2.

Let be a partitioned -formula. Suppose there are finitely many -formulas such that for every model of and every , there are and such that is a -definition for . Then has a uniform definition.

2.3. Background in valued fields

For a valued field we let denote the value group, its valuation ring, the residue field and the residue map. Given a valued field extension and a subset , we say that is -valuation independent if for every -linear combination with , . The extension is called -defectlessFootnote1 if every finitely generated -vector subspace of admits a -valuation basis, that is, a -valuation independent set which spans over .

1

This is the same as “separated” in W. Baur’s and F. Delon’s terminology.

Let be the language of rings and be its extension by a binary predicate . We let be the -theory of algebraically closed (non-trivially) valued fields, where is interpreted in a valued field by . Recall this theory has quantifier elimination (see also Reference 12).

We let be the -theory of a finite extension of with -ramification index and residue degree . Here is together with new constants symbols interpreted in any model by elements which modulo form an -basis of (see Reference 20). Recall this theory admits quantifier elimination by adding predicates for -powers (see Reference 20, Theorem 5.6).

Finally, the theory is the theory of real closed (non-trivially) valued fields in which the valuation ring is convex with respect to the ordering. It has quantifier elimination by results in Reference 3.

3. Completions by definable types

3.1. The definable completion

Let be a -definable set and be a small set containing . The definable completion of over , denoted , is the space of -definable global types which concentrate on . For a tuple of variables we write for .

Convention 3.1.

In what follows, to simply notation, we will drop the index in and simply write . Keep in mind that with this notation is not a subset of but a subset of . No conflict in notation will occur, as we will never consider as a subset of .

Given a -definable function , it is easy to see that the image of a definable type under is again definable. We will therefore use the more functorial notation for every small set containing .

Remark 3.2.
(1)

Note that if is injective, so is and hence . However, the transfer of surjectivity from to is more subtle. We will say that has surjectivity transfer precisely if for every surjective definable function , the function is surjective. Note that if has definable Skolem functions, then it has surjectivity transfer. Indeed, let be a definable section of . Then, given any type , we have that , so is surjective. We do not know whether has surjectivity transfer.

(2)

In Reference 13, the authors considered the following variant: say has the extension property if is surjective for every surjective pro-definable map between pro-definable subsets (see Section 4.1). One can check that the latter is equivalent to surjectivity transfer. We refrain from using the expression “extension property” to avoid confusion with various occurrences of this term throughout model theory.

(3)

By Reference 13, Lemma 4.2.6, a stronger result holds for o-minimal theories and . Indeed, the function is surjective even when and are definable subsets of products of imaginary sorts. Adapting the argument given in Reference 13, Lemma 4.2.6(a), the same result holds for .

3.2. Other completions by definable types

3.2.1. The bounded completion

Let be an o-minimal theory and be a model of . Given an elementary extension , we say that is bounded by if for every , there are such that . Let be a small subset of and be a definable set. A type is bounded if for any small model containing and every realization , there is an elementary extension with and such that is bounded by .

Let be either or a completion of . Let be a small subset of . A type is bounded if for any small model containing and every realization , is bounded by , where denotes the value group sort.

Finally, let be either an o-minimal theory, a completion of or . Let be a small subset of and be a definable set. The bounded completion of over , denoted , is the set of bounded global -definable types.

3.2.2. The orthogonal completion

Let be either a completion of or . Let be a small subset of . A type is said to be orthogonal to if for every model containing and every realization , . Given a definable set , the orthogonal completion of , denoted by , is the set of global -definable types concentrating on which are orthogonal to .

In Reference 13, the set is called the stable completion of over . The name arises since, in this context, also corresponds to the set of definable types over which are stably dominated, and equivalently, which are generically stable (see Reference 13, Proposition 2.9.1). However, such an equivalence does not hold in : every generically stable type (resp. stably dominated) must be a realized type.

Remark 3.3.
(1)

If is an o-minimal expansion of the theory of real closed fields, then every bounded definable type is a realized type. However, this is not the case for general o-minimal theories. For example, the type of an element arbitrarily close to zero in is bounded.

(2)

Let be either a completion of or , and let a model of . If is orthogonal to , then is orthogonal to for every .

(3)

Given a definable function , then the pushforward of restricted to (resp. to ) has image in (resp. ). We use (resp. ) to denote the restriction of to (resp. ).

3.2.3. Geometric interpretation

For a completion of , let be a variety over a complete rank 1 valued field . In Reference 13, is introduced as a model-theoretic analogue of the Berkovich analytification of . Similarly, our aim is to view as a model-theoretic analogue of the Huber analytification of . When is , is a good candidate to be the model-theoretic counterpart of the analytification of semi-algebraic sets defined by Jell, Scheiderer and Yu in Reference 14. The set is also tightly related to the set of residue field dominated types as defined by Ealy, Haskell and Maříková in Reference 9. The space (in ) seems to suggest there is an analogue of Huber’s analytification of semi-algebraic sets. Finally, can be viewed as a model-theoretic analogue of the “space of valuations on ”. As mentioned in the introduction, we will present more structural results concerning these spaces in a sequel of this article.

4. Spaces of definable types as pro-definable sets

4.1. Pro-definable sets and morphisms

Let be a small upwards directed partially ordered set and be a small subset of . A -definable projective system is a collection such that:

(1)

for every , is a -definable set;

(2)

for every such that ; is -definable;

(3)

is the identity on and for all .

A pro--definable set is the projective limit of a -definable projective system . We say that is pro-definable if it is pro--definable for some small set of parameters . Pro-definable sets can also be seen as -definable sets. By a result of Kamensky Reference 15, we may identify and .

Let and be two pro--definable sets with associated -definable projective systems and . A pro--definable morphism is the data of a monotone function and a family of -definable functions such that, for all in and all in with and , it holds that .

4.2. Completions by definable types as pro-definable sets

What does it mean that a completion by definable types is pro-definable? Let us give the precise meaning of this in the case of the definable completion. The other completions are handled analogously.

We say that definable types are pro-definable in if, for every set of parameters and for every -definable set , there is a pro--definable (possibly in ) set and a bijection for every model containing . Further, we require some functoriality: if is an elementary extension of , we have natural maps and ; and if is an -definable function, then there are pro--definable morphisms and making the following diagram commute

Similarly, we say a subfunctor of is pro-definable if it satisfies the same conditions after replacing with in the above diagram. It is in this sense that we say that the bounded and orthogonal completions are pro-definable (note in both cases we have a subfunctor by Remark 3.3).

The following result, essentially due to E. Hrushovski and F. Loeser Reference 13, Lemma 2.5.1, shows the link between uniform definability of types and pro-definability. We include a proof for the reader’s convenience.

Proposition 4.1.

Suppose has uniform definability of types. Then definable types are pro-definable in . In particular, if has elimination of imaginaries, then definable types are pro-definable in .

Proof.

Fix some model of . Given a partitioned -formula , let be a uniform definition for . By possibly using an -formula, we may suppose that is a single variable and

Let denote the set of partitioned -formulas of the form where ranges over all finite tuples of variables. We associate to this data a map defined by

where is such that is a -definition for . The codomain of , being a small product of definable sets, is pro-definable. Thus, since is injective, to obtain pro-definability it suffices to show that is -definable.

Without loss of generality we may suppose that the map factors through Boolean combinations, that is, and . Consider the following set of formulas containing, for each -formula , the formula given by

Given  in , let be the tuple and denote the conjunction . Since factors through conjunctions

We claim that

From left-to-right, let and be a formula in . We have that

and the last formula holds since for every any realization of satisfies such a formula. To show the right-to-left inclusion, let be such that . Consider the set of formulas

Let us show that is an element of . Once we show is consistent, that follows by definition. Let be formulas in . Letting , by the definition of and Equation E1 we have that the formula is also in . Moreover, since we have in particular that

Finally, since , we must have that , which shows there is an element satisfying . By compactness, is consistent.

Given an -definable subset , we endow with the pro-definable structure inherited from . More precisely, if is defined by a formula for some tuple , we have that

We leave as an exercise to show that the present construction guarantees all the above functoriality properties.

Corollary 4.2.

Suppose has uniform definability of types. Let be a model and be a definable subset of . Then every -definable subset of is pro-definable.

Remark 4.3.

If has uniform definability of types and has surjectivity transfer for definable functions in (see (3) of Remark 3.2), then definable types concentrating on a product of imaginary sorts are also uniformly definable. In particular, by Proposition 4.1, if is a definable subset of some product of imaginary sorts, then is pro-definable (in ).

5. Stably embedded pairs and elementarity

Suppose is a one-sorted language. Let be a language extending by a new unary predicate . We denote an -structure as a pair where is an -structure and corresponds to the interpretation of . Given a complete -theory , the -theory of elementary pairs of models of , is denoted . Given a tuple , we abuse of notation and write as an abbreviation for . When is multi-sorted we let denote the language which extends by a new unary predicate for every -sort . Analogously, an -structure is a model of if the collection of subsets forms an elementary -substructure of . We will also denote any such a structure as a pair where and for every -sort , .

5.1. Stable embedded pairs

Let be an elementary extension of models of . The extension is called stably embedded if for every -definable subset , the set is -definable in .

The class of stably embedded models of will be denoted . It is a standard exercise to show that is stably embedded if and only if for every tuple in , the type is definable.

Our main objective is to show that for various NIP theories , is an -elementary class. Stable theories constitute a trivial example of this phenomenon, since the class of stably embedded pairs coincides with the class of elementary pairs. O-minimal theories constitute a less trivial example. Let us first recall Marker-Steinhorn’s characterizarion of definable types in o-minimal structures.

Theorem 5.1 (Reference 16, Theorem 2.1).

Let be an o-minimal theory and be a model of . Then, is definable if and only if for every realization of , is Dedekind complete in (where is the prime model of over ).

Since the Dedekind completeness of the small structure of a pair is expressible in , we readily obtain:

Corollary 5.2.

Let be a complete o-minimal theory. Then the class of stably embedded pairs is -elementary.

The following result of Q. Brouette shows the analogue result for .

Theorem 5.3 (Reference 2, Proposition 3.6).

Let be a model of . Then, is definable if and only if for every realization of , is Dedekind complete in the real closure of the ordered differential field generated by .

Corollary 5.4.

The class of stably embedded pairs of models of is -elementary.

The following characterization of definable types in -groups (i.e. models of Presburger arithmetic) is due to G. Conant and S. Vojdani (see Reference 5).

Theorem 5.5.

Let be a -group. Then, is definable if and only if for every realization , is an end-extension.

Corollary 5.6.

The class of stably embedded models of Presburger arithmetic -elementary.

5.2. Stable embedded pairs of valued fields

In what follows we gather the corresponding characterization of stably embedded pairs of models for , and . We follow the notations introduced in Section 2.3. We need first the following terminology for induced structures. Let be an -structure and be an imaginary sort in . We let be the language having a predicate for every -definable (without parameters) subset . The structure in which every is interpreted as the set is called the induced structure on . The sort is called stably embedded if every -definable subset of a cartesian power of is -definable. The following lemma is left to the reader.

Lemma 5.7.

Let be an complete -theory and be a stably embedded pair of models of . Let be an -sort which is stably embedded (as a sort) in every model of . Then the pair is stably embedded in .

Corollary 5.8.

Let be or a completion of . Let be a stably embedded pair of models of . Then, the pairs and are stably embedded in their induced structure languages.

Proof.

By Lemma 5.7, it suffices to show that in each of these theories the value group and the residue field are stably embedded (as sorts). This follows by Reference 12, Proposition 2.1.3 for , Reference 17, Lemma 3.13 for , and Reference 4, Theorem 6 for ).

Let us now explain how to show that the class is -elementary for either , or . In all three cases, the result will follow from the following theorem:

Theorem 5.9.

Let be either , or . Let be a pair of models of . Then the following are equivalent

(1)

the pair is stably embedded

(2)

the valued field extension is -defectless, the pairs and are stably embedded.

For the above Theorem is precisely the content of Reference 6, Theorem 1.9. For and the result is new and the corresponding proof is presented in Sections 5.2.1 and 5.2.2.

Corollary 5.10.

Let be either , or . Then the class is elementary in the language of pairs.

Proof.

By Theorem 5.9, it suffices to show that the condition stated in part (2) is elementary in the language of pairs. Note that being a -defectless extension is an elementary property in the language of pairs, so we only need to show that having stably embedded value group and residue field extensions is an elementary property in the language of pairs.

Concerning the value group, both in and , the value group extension is an elementary extension of divisible ordered abelian groups and therefore, being stably embedded is elementary by Corollary 5.2 and Corollary 5.8. For , the value group extension is an extension of models of Presburger arithmetic, and hence the result follows by Corollary 5.6.

Regarding the residue field extension, note that it only plays a role for (indeed, in the residue field is a pure algebraically closed field, hence stable, and in the residue field is finite). In , the residue field extension corresponds to a stably embedded pair of real closed fields. As before, the result follows by Corollary 5.2 and Corollary 5.8.

Some of these results were recently extended by P. Touchard to other classes of Henselian fields, see Reference 22.

5.2.1. Stably embedded pairs of real closed valued fields

Proof of Theorem 5.9 for .

Let be a pair of real closed valued fields.

: By Corollary 5.8, the pairs and are stably embedded. That the extension is -defectless follows word for word the proof for given in Reference 6, Theorem 1.9 (it uses that the pair of value groups is a pair of pure divisible ordered abelian groups (see Reference 17, Lemma 3.13). Alternatively, since every model of has an elementary extension which is maximal (as a valued field), one can argue as in Reference 22, Prop. 2.4.

: Let be an -definable set over . We need to show that is -definable over . By quantifier elimination, we may suppose that is defined by one of the following formulas

with either or ,

,

where with .

Let be a valuation basis for the -vector space generated by the coefficients of and . For write and , with . It then follows that for any one has

For (i), the result follows from Equation 5.1 and stable embeddedness of the pair (for more details, see Reference 6, pages 40-41).

For (ii), multiplying the by suitable elements in , we can further suppose that for every , if and lie in the same coset modulo , then . Moreover, at the expense of multiplying by , we can suppose that for all .

For each , let be the set

By case , we may suppose is definable over . Further, since is -valuation independent, the sets cover when varies over all non-empty subsets of . Therefore, it suffices to show that is definable over for every . Let us first show how to reduce to the case where . If , then for all we have, since the valuation is compatible with the ordering,

and thus we obtain an equivalent formula where for all , is the same. Therefore without loss of generality it suffices to show the case . Now, since for all , for all , and are in the same coset modulo , and hence for all . Also for all . Multiplying by a suitable constant , we may suppose that for all . Similarly, multiplying by a suitable constant , we may suppose that for all . We conclude by noting that in this situation, for all

Since is stably embedded in , the set is definable over . Lifting the parameters, we obtain that is definable over .

5.2.2. Stably embedded pairs of models of

Let be a model of . We need some preliminary lemmas.

Lemma 5.11.

Let be a valued field extension. Suppose that every is of the form with and such that . Then the extension is -defectless.

Proof.

Let be a -vector space of dimension . Let us show that contains elements such that all lie in distinct -cosets. By Reference 10, Lemma 3.2.2, this implies that is a -valuation basis for . We proceed by induction on . Let be a basis for . For the result is trivial (take ). Then, by induction, the -vector space generated by contains elements such that each lies in a different -coset. Without loss of generality we may assume

If either , , or

for some , then we are done by setting . Otherwise, there are and such that . By assumption, there is be such that with . Therefore, satisfies . If is in a different -coset than every for , we are done by setting . Otherwise, there are and such that . Following the same procedure, one finds a -linear combination such that is in a different -coset than every for .

Let be a valued field extension. Let be the convex hull of in and be the valuation on obtained by composing with the canonical quotient map . Let us denote and the residue fields of and . As is trivial on , .

An element is limit over if the extension is an immediate extension. We let the reader check that if is a model of and is limit over , then the type is not definable.

Theorem 5.12 (Reference 8, Part (a) of the main Theorem).

Suppose is a valued field extension of Henselian valued fields of characteristic 0 and let be as above. If the canonical embedding is an isomorphism, then is stably embedded in .

Proof of Theorem 5.9 for .

: That is stably embedded follows by Corollary 5.8. It remains to show that the extension is -defectless. By Lemma 5.11, it suffices to show that every element is of the form for and such that . Every element is of this form (with ), so we may suppose . If take . Otherwise, since by Theorem 5.5 is an end extension of , we must have . Suppose there is no such that . Thus, for every , . But this implies that is limit over , which contradicts that is stably embedded in . This shows the extension is -defectless.

: Since the pair is -defectless, there are no limit points in over . Moreover, since is stably embedded, by Theorem 5.5, it is an end extension of . The same argument as in the previous implication shows that every element is of the form for and such that . In particular, the convex hull of in is . Let us show that is isomorphic to . For all such that , there is a unique such that . Therefore , which shows that is in bijection with . The result now follows from Theorem 5.12.

We summarize the above results in the following theorem.

Theorem 5.13.

Let be one of the following theories: a complete o-minimal theory; ; Presburger arithmetic; ; ; a completion of . Then, the class is an elementary class in .

Question 5.14.

Is there a natural characterization of the class of complete NIP theories for which is -elementary?

Note that there are NIP -theories for which the class is not -elementary. The following example is due to L. Newelski.

Example 5.15.

Let be an increasing sequence of irrational numbers with the limit irrational. Consider the structure where is a unary predicate interpreted as the cut . The theory is NIP as any NIP theory extended by externally definable sets is NIP (see Reference 21, Section 3.3). Now let where realizes the definable type over determined by the set of formulas

Then, is a stably embedded pair. Let be an ultrapower of over a non-principal ultrafilter over . Let be the class of the sequence modulo . We let the reader check that the set is not definable in , hence the pair is not stably embedded.

6. Uniform definability via classes of pairs

The following theorem provides an abstract criterion for a theory to have uniform definability of types.

Theorem 6.1.

Suppose there is an -elementary class such that

if , then ;

if , then is an -substructure of an -elementary extension of ;

if , and is a finite tuple in , then is definable (where is defined with respect to );

for every small model and every definable type , there is a pair and such that .

Then has uniform definability of types. In particular, definable types are pro-definable in in any reduct of in which has elimination of imaginaries.

Proof.

Fix a partitioned -formula . Let be an enumeration of all -formulas having among their free variables. Suppose for a contradiction that no formula provides a uniform definition for . This implies, by Lemma 2.2, that for every finite subset there are a model of and a type such that no formula with is a -definition for . Consider for every the -formula

Let , where is an -axiomatization of . Let us show that is consistent. Let be a finite subset of and let . By assumption, there is some such that no with is a -definition for . By condition , let be an element of and be such that . By the choice of , we have that holds for all . This shows that is consistent. Thus, by compactness, is consistent.

Let be an element in and be a realization of . By the definition of , the type is not definable, which contradicts .

Corollary 6.2.

Let be an -theory such that

is -elementary;

for every small model and every definable type , there is a stably embedded such that is realized in .

Then has uniform definability of types. In particular, definable types are pro-definable in in any reduct of in which has elimination of imaginaries.

Proof.

This follows directly by Theorem 6.1 by taking . Indeed, note that conditions of Theorem 6.1 are trivially satisfied, and condition corresponds to the present assumption .

Theorem 6.3.

The following theories have uniform definability of types (in one of their natural languages):

(1)

any complete stable theory;

(2)

any complete o-minimal theory;

(3)

Presburger arithmetic;

(4)

The theory of a finite extension of ;

(5)

;

(6)

any completion of ;

(7)

.

Proof.

(1) This is a well-known result (see B. Poizat’s paper Reference 19). Alternatively, one could also use Corollary 6.2: condition is trivially satisfied and for condition take .

Let be one of the theories from (2)-(6). We apply Corollary 6.2. Condition is granted by Theorem 5.13. For condition (ii), let be a model of , and be a realization of . If is o-minimal, by Marker-Steinhorn’s theorem (Theorem 5.1), we can take since is already stably embedded. For a theory from (3)-(6) we take . Note that in these cases is indeed a model of and the extension is stably embedded by Lemma 2.1. This completes the result for .

For , the structure is a real closed field extension of but it is not necessarily a model of . To ensure condition we can apply the following idea of E. Kaplan. Let be a sufficiently large real closed field containing and such that the extension is a stably embedded extension of real closed fields. By Reference 11, Proposition 4.11, there is a derivation on extending the derivation on such that is a model of . By Reference 2, Proposition 3.6, the extension of models of is stably embedded (in the language of ).

Theorem 6.4.

Let be an -theory listed in Theorem 6.2 and be any reduct of in which has elimination of imaginaries. Then, definable types in are pro-definable in .

Proof.

This follows directly by Theorem 6.2 and Proposition 4.1.

We expect similar results hold for theories of (tame) valued fields with generic derivations as defined in Reference 7 and for theories of o-minimal fields with a generic derivation as defined in Reference 11.

Corollary 6.5.

Let be either an o-minimal theory, a completion of or . The bounded completion of a definable set is pro-definable in . In the two latter cases, the orthogonal completion of a definable set is pro-definable in

Proof.

Both cases are similar, we will just work with the bounded case and leave the other to the reader. By Corollary 4.2 it suffices to show that is -definable inside , for a given -definable set . Suppose . For every formula where is a -variable, for every such that defines a function , and for every , there is such that contains the formula . Let be the formula

and be its uniform definition. Let be the canonical parameter such that is the -definition of . Let denote the formula . Then if and only if for each formula and associated formulas and as above

which shows is an -definable subset of .

Question.

Can one characterize NIP theories (or -minimal theories) having uniform definability of types (resp. definable types are pro-definable)?

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank: S. Starchenko and Y. Peterzil for motivating the study spaces of definable types using pairs; M. Hils for interesting discussions; L. Newelski for sharing with us Example 5.15; and E. Kaplan for pointing out a proof of Theorem 6.3 for .

Mathematical Fragments

Lemma 2.1.

If is definable and , then is definable.

Lemma 2.2.

Let be a partitioned -formula. Suppose there are finitely many -formulas such that for every model of and every , there are and such that is a -definition for . Then has a uniform definition.

Remark 3.2.
(1)

Note that if is injective, so is and hence . However, the transfer of surjectivity from to is more subtle. We will say that has surjectivity transfer precisely if for every surjective definable function , the function is surjective. Note that if has definable Skolem functions, then it has surjectivity transfer. Indeed, let be a definable section of . Then, given any type , we have that , so is surjective. We do not know whether has surjectivity transfer.

(2)

In Reference 13, the authors considered the following variant: say has the extension property if is surjective for every surjective pro-definable map between pro-definable subsets (see Section 4.1). One can check that the latter is equivalent to surjectivity transfer. We refrain from using the expression “extension property” to avoid confusion with various occurrences of this term throughout model theory.

(3)

By Reference 13, Lemma 4.2.6, a stronger result holds for o-minimal theories and . Indeed, the function is surjective even when and are definable subsets of products of imaginary sorts. Adapting the argument given in Reference 13, Lemma 4.2.6(a), the same result holds for .

Remark 3.3.
(1)

If is an o-minimal expansion of the theory of real closed fields, then every bounded definable type is a realized type. However, this is not the case for general o-minimal theories. For example, the type of an element arbitrarily close to zero in is bounded.

(2)

Let be either a completion of or , and let a model of . If is orthogonal to , then is orthogonal to for every .

(3)

Given a definable function , then the pushforward of restricted to (resp. to ) has image in (resp. ). We use (resp. ) to denote the restriction of to (resp. ).

Proposition 4.1.

Suppose has uniform definability of types. Then definable types are pro-definable in . In particular, if has elimination of imaginaries, then definable types are pro-definable in .

Equation (E1)
Corollary 4.2.

Suppose has uniform definability of types. Let be a model and be a definable subset of . Then every -definable subset of is pro-definable.

Theorem 5.1 (Reference 16, Theorem 2.1).

Let be an o-minimal theory and be a model of . Then, is definable if and only if for every realization of , is Dedekind complete in (where is the prime model of over ).

Corollary 5.2.

Let be a complete o-minimal theory. Then the class of stably embedded pairs is -elementary.

Theorem 5.5.

Let be a -group. Then, is definable if and only if for every realization , is an end-extension.

Corollary 5.6.

The class of stably embedded models of Presburger arithmetic -elementary.

Lemma 5.7.

Let be an complete -theory and be a stably embedded pair of models of . Let be an -sort which is stably embedded (as a sort) in every model of . Then the pair is stably embedded in .

Corollary 5.8.

Let be or a completion of . Let be a stably embedded pair of models of . Then, the pairs and are stably embedded in their induced structure languages.

Theorem 5.9.

Let be either , or . Let be a pair of models of . Then the following are equivalent

(1)

the pair is stably embedded

(2)

the valued field extension is -defectless, the pairs and are stably embedded.

Equation (5.1)
Lemma 5.11.

Let be a valued field extension. Suppose that every is of the form with and such that . Then the extension is -defectless.

Theorem 5.12 (Reference 8, Part (a) of the main Theorem).

Suppose is a valued field extension of Henselian valued fields of characteristic 0 and let be as above. If the canonical embedding is an isomorphism, then is stably embedded in .

Theorem 5.13.

Let be one of the following theories: a complete o-minimal theory; ; Presburger arithmetic; ; ; a completion of . Then, the class is an elementary class in .

Example 5.15.

Let be an increasing sequence of irrational numbers with the limit irrational. Consider the structure where is a unary predicate interpreted as the cut . The theory is NIP as any NIP theory extended by externally definable sets is NIP (see Reference 21, Section 3.3). Now let where realizes the definable type over determined by the set of formulas

Then, is a stably embedded pair. Let be an ultrapower of over a non-principal ultrafilter over . Let be the class of the sequence modulo . We let the reader check that the set is not definable in , hence the pair is not stably embedded.

Theorem 6.1.

Suppose there is an -elementary class such that

if , then ;

if , then is an -substructure of an -elementary extension of ;

if , and is a finite tuple in , then is definable (where is defined with respect to );

for every small model and every definable type , there is a pair and such that .

Then has uniform definability of types. In particular, definable types are pro-definable in in any reduct of in which has elimination of imaginaries.

Corollary 6.2.

Let be an -theory such that

is -elementary;

for every small model and every definable type , there is a stably embedded such that is realized in .

Then has uniform definability of types. In particular, definable types are pro-definable in in any reduct of in which has elimination of imaginaries.

Theorem 6.3.

The following theories have uniform definability of types (in one of their natural languages):

(1)

any complete stable theory;

(2)

any complete o-minimal theory;

(3)

Presburger arithmetic;

(4)

The theory of a finite extension of ;

(5)

;

(6)

any completion of ;

(7)

.

Theorem 6.4.

Let be an -theory listed in Theorem 6.2 and be any reduct of in which has elimination of imaginaries. Then, definable types in are pro-definable in .

References

Reference [1]
Vladimir G. Berkovich, Smooth -adic analytic spaces are locally contractible, Invent. Math. 137 (1999), no. 1, 1–84, DOI 10.1007/s002220050323. MR1702143,
Show rawAMSref \bib{Berkovich_contractible}{article}{ author={Berkovich, Vladimir G.}, title={Smooth $p$-adic analytic spaces are locally contractible}, journal={Invent. Math.}, volume={137}, date={1999}, number={1}, pages={1--84}, issn={0020-9910}, review={\MR {1702143}}, doi={10.1007/s002220050323}, }
Reference [2]
Quentin Brouette, Definable types in the theory of closed ordered differential fields, Arch. Math. Logic 56 (2017), no. 1-2, 119–129, DOI 10.1007/s00153-016-0517-4. MR3598799,
Show rawAMSref \bib{brouette}{article}{ author={Brouette, Quentin}, title={Definable types in the theory of closed ordered differential fields}, journal={Arch. Math. Logic}, volume={56}, date={2017}, number={1-2}, pages={119--129}, issn={0933-5846}, review={\MR {3598799}}, doi={10.1007/s00153-016-0517-4}, }
Reference [3]
Gregory Cherlin and Max A. Dickmann, Real closed rings. II. Model theory, Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 25 (1983), no. 3, 213–231, DOI 10.1016/0168-0072(83)90019-2. MR730855,
Show rawAMSref \bib{cherlin_dickmann}{article}{ author={Cherlin, Gregory}, author={Dickmann, Max A.}, title={Real closed rings. II. Model theory}, journal={Ann. Pure Appl. Logic}, volume={25}, date={1983}, number={3}, pages={213--231}, issn={0168-0072}, review={\MR {730855}}, doi={10.1016/0168-0072(83)90019-2}, }
Reference [4]
Raf Cluckers, Presburger sets and -minimal fields, J. Symbolic Logic 68 (2003), no. 1, 153–162, DOI 10.2178/jsl/1045861509. MR1959315,
Show rawAMSref \bib{clu-presb03}{article}{ author={Cluckers, Raf}, title={Presburger sets and $p$-minimal fields}, journal={J. Symbolic Logic}, volume={68}, date={2003}, number={1}, pages={153--162}, issn={0022-4812}, review={\MR {1959315}}, doi={10.2178/jsl/1045861509}, }
Reference [5]
Gabriel Conant and Somayeh Vojdani, Definable types and f-generics in Presburger arithmetic, available at https://www.dpmms.cam.ac.uk/~gc610/Math/presburger_note.pdf.
Reference [6]
Pablo Cubides Kovacsics and Françoise Delon, Definable types in algebraically closed valued fields, MLQ Math. Log. Q. 62 (2016), no. 1-2, 35–45, DOI 10.1002/malq.201400039. MR3472177,
Show rawAMSref \bib{CD}{article}{ author={Cubides Kovacsics, Pablo}, author={Delon, Fran\c {c}oise}, title={Definable types in algebraically closed valued fields}, journal={MLQ Math. Log. Q.}, volume={62}, date={2016}, number={1-2}, pages={35--45}, issn={0942-5616}, review={\MR {3472177}}, doi={10.1002/malq.201400039}, }
Reference [7]
Pablo Cubides Kovacsics and Françoise Point, Topological fields with a generic derivation, arXiv:1912.07912 [math.LO], 2020.
Reference [8]
Françoise Delon, Définissabilité avec paramètres extérieurs dans et (French, with English summary), Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 106 (1989), no. 1, 193–198, DOI 10.2307/2047391. MR953003,
Show rawAMSref \bib{delon}{article}{ author={Delon, Fran\c {c}oise}, title={D\'{e}finissabilit\'{e} avec param\`etres ext\'{e}rieurs dans ${\mathbf {Q}}_p$ et ${\mathbf {R}}$}, language={French, with English summary}, journal={Proc. Amer. Math. Soc.}, volume={106}, date={1989}, number={1}, pages={193--198}, issn={0002-9939}, review={\MR {953003}}, doi={10.2307/2047391}, }
Reference [9]
Clifton Ealy, Deirdre Haskell, and Jana Maříková, Residue field domination in real closed valued fields, Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 60 (2019), no. 3, 333–351, DOI 10.1215/00294527-2019-0015. MR3985616,
Show rawAMSref \bib{cli-has-mari}{article}{ author={Ealy, Clifton}, author={Haskell, Deirdre}, author={Ma\v {r}\'{\i }kov\'{a}, Jana}, title={Residue field domination in real closed valued fields}, journal={Notre Dame J. Form. Log.}, volume={60}, date={2019}, number={3}, pages={333--351}, issn={0029-4527}, review={\MR {3985616}}, doi={10.1215/00294527-2019-0015}, }
Reference [10]
Antonio J. Engler and Alexander Prestel, Valued fields, Springer Monographs in Mathematics, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 2005. MR2183496,
Show rawAMSref \bib{prestel2005}{book}{ author={Engler, Antonio J.}, author={Prestel, Alexander}, title={Valued fields}, series={Springer Monographs in Mathematics}, publisher={Springer-Verlag, Berlin}, date={2005}, pages={x+205}, isbn={978-3-540-24221-5}, isbn={3-540-24221-X}, review={\MR {2183496}}, }
Reference [11]
Antongiulio Fornasiero and Elliot Kaplan, Generic derivations on o-minimal structures, arXiv:1905.07298 [math.LO], 2019.
Reference [12]
Deirdre Haskell, Ehud Hrushovski, and Dugald Macpherson, Definable sets in algebraically closed valued fields: elimination of imaginaries, J. Reine Angew. Math. 597 (2006), 175–236, DOI 10.1515/CRELLE.2006.066. MR2264318,
Show rawAMSref \bib{HHM}{article}{ author={Haskell, Deirdre}, author={Hrushovski, Ehud}, author={Macpherson, Dugald}, title={Definable sets in algebraically closed valued fields: elimination of imaginaries}, journal={J. Reine Angew. Math.}, volume={597}, date={2006}, pages={175--236}, issn={0075-4102}, review={\MR {2264318}}, doi={10.1515/CRELLE.2006.066}, }
Reference [13]
Ehud Hrushovski and François Loeser, Non-archimedean tame topology and stably dominated types, Annals of Mathematics Studies, vol. 192, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2016, DOI 10.1515/9781400881222. MR3445772,
Show rawAMSref \bib{HL}{book}{ author={Hrushovski, Ehud}, author={Loeser, Fran\c {c}ois}, title={Non-archimedean tame topology and stably dominated types}, series={Annals of Mathematics Studies}, volume={192}, publisher={Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ}, date={2016}, pages={vii+216}, isbn={978-0-691-16169-3}, isbn={978-0-691-16168-6}, review={\MR {3445772}}, doi={10.1515/9781400881222}, }
Reference [14]
Philipp Jell, Claus Scheiderer, and Josephine Yu, Real Tropicalization and Analytification of Semialgebraic Sets, International Mathematics Research Notices (2020), rnaa112.
Reference [15]
Moshe Kamensky, Ind- and pro- definable sets, Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 147 (2007), no. 3, 180–186, DOI 10.1016/j.apal.2007.04.003. MR2335085,
Show rawAMSref \bib{kamensky}{article}{ author={Kamensky, Moshe}, title={Ind- and pro- definable sets}, journal={Ann. Pure Appl. Logic}, volume={147}, date={2007}, number={3}, pages={180--186}, issn={0168-0072}, review={\MR {2335085}}, doi={10.1016/j.apal.2007.04.003}, }
Reference [16]
David Marker and Charles I. Steinhorn, Definable types in -minimal theories, J. Symbolic Logic 59 (1994), no. 1, 185–198, DOI 10.2307/2275260. MR1264974,
Show rawAMSref \bib{MS}{article}{ author={Marker, David}, author={Steinhorn, Charles I.}, title={Definable types in $\mathcal {O}$-minimal theories}, journal={J. Symbolic Logic}, volume={59}, date={1994}, number={1}, pages={185--198}, issn={0022-4812}, review={\MR {1264974}}, doi={10.2307/2275260}, }
Reference [17]
T. Mellor, Imaginaries in real closed valued fields, Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 139 (2006), no. 1-3, 230–279, DOI 10.1016/j.apal.2005.05.014. MR2206257,
Show rawAMSref \bib{mellor}{article}{ author={Mellor, T.}, title={Imaginaries in real closed valued fields}, journal={Ann. Pure Appl. Logic}, volume={139}, date={2006}, number={1-3}, pages={230--279}, issn={0168-0072}, review={\MR {2206257}}, doi={10.1016/j.apal.2005.05.014}, }
Reference [18]
Anand Pillay, An introduction to stability theory, Oxford Logic Guides, vol. 8, The Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press, New York, 1983. MR719195,
Show rawAMSref \bib{pillay83}{book}{ author={Pillay, Anand}, title={An introduction to stability theory}, series={Oxford Logic Guides}, volume={8}, publisher={The Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press, New York}, date={1983}, pages={xii+146}, isbn={0-19-853186-9}, review={\MR {719195}}, }
Reference [19]
Bruno Poizat, Paires de structures stables (French), J. Symbolic Logic 48 (1983), no. 2, 239–249, DOI 10.2307/2273543. MR704080,
Show rawAMSref \bib{poizat}{article}{ author={Poizat, Bruno}, title={Paires de structures stables}, language={French}, journal={J. Symbolic Logic}, volume={48}, date={1983}, number={2}, pages={239--249}, issn={0022-4812}, review={\MR {704080}}, doi={10.2307/2273543}, }
Reference [20]
Alexander Prestel and Peter Roquette, Formally -adic fields, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 1050, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1984, DOI 10.1007/BFb0071461. MR738076,
Show rawAMSref \bib{pres-roque}{book}{ author={Prestel, Alexander}, author={Roquette, Peter}, title={Formally $p$-adic fields}, series={Lecture Notes in Mathematics}, volume={1050}, publisher={Springer-Verlag, Berlin}, date={1984}, pages={v+167}, isbn={3-540-12890-5}, review={\MR {738076}}, doi={10.1007/BFb0071461}, }
Reference [21]
Pierre Simon, A guide to NIP theories, Lecture Notes in Logic, vol. 44, Association for Symbolic Logic, Chicago, IL; Cambridge Scientific Publishers, Cambridge, 2015, DOI 10.1017/CBO9781107415133. MR3560428,
Show rawAMSref \bib{simon}{book}{ author={Simon, Pierre}, title={A guide to NIP theories}, series={Lecture Notes in Logic}, volume={44}, publisher={Association for Symbolic Logic, Chicago, IL; Cambridge Scientific Publishers, Cambridge}, date={2015}, pages={vii+156}, isbn={978-1-107-05775-3}, review={\MR {3560428}}, doi={10.1017/CBO9781107415133}, }
Reference [22]
Pierre Touchard, Stably embedded submodels of henselian valued fields, arXiv preprint arXiv:2005.02363 (2020).

Article Information

MSC 2020
Primary: 11S80 (Other analytic theory (analogues of beta and gamma functions, -adic integration, etc.))
Secondary: 11U09 (Model theory (number-theoretic aspects))
Keywords
  • Pro-definability
  • definable types
  • stably embedded pairs
Author Information
Pablo Cubides Kovacsics
Mathematisches Institut der Heinrich-Heine-Universität Düsseldorf, Universitätsstr. 1, 40225 Düsseldorf, Germany
ORCID
MathSciNet
Jinhe Ye
Institut de Mathématiques de Jussieu-Paris Rive Gauche, Sorbonne Université - Campus Pierre et Marie Curie 4, place Jussieu - Boite Courrier 247 75252 Paris Cedex 05
jinhe.ye@imj-prg.fr
ORCID
MathSciNet
Additional Notes

The first author was partially supported by the ERC project TOSSIBERG (Grant Agreement 637027), ERC project MOTMELSUM (Grant agreement 615722) and individual research grant Archimedische und nicht-archimedische Stratifizierungen höherer Ordnung, funded by the DFG. The second author was partially supported by NSF research grant DMS1500671.

Communicated by
Heike Mildenberger
Journal Information
Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, Series B, Volume 8, Issue 15, ISSN 2330-1511, published by the American Mathematical Society, Providence, Rhode Island.
Publication History
This article was received on , revised on , , and published on .
Copyright Information
Copyright 2021 by the authors under Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial 3.0 License (CC BY NC 3.0)
Article References
  • Permalink
  • Permalink (PDF)
  • DOI 10.1090/bproc/85
  • MathSciNet Review: 4273164
  • Show rawAMSref \bib{4273164}{article}{ author={Cubides Kovacsics, Pablo}, author={Ye, Jinhe}, title={Pro-definability of spaces of definable types}, journal={Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. Ser. B}, volume={8}, number={15}, date={2021}, pages={173-188}, issn={2330-1511}, review={4273164}, doi={10.1090/bproc/85}, }

Settings

Change font size
Resize article panel
Enable equation enrichment

Note. To explore an equation, focus it (e.g., by clicking on it) and use the arrow keys to navigate its structure. Screenreader users should be advised that enabling speech synthesis will lead to duplicate aural rendering.

For more information please visit the AMS MathViewer documentation.