On the linearity of lattices in affine buildings and ergodicity of the singular Cartan flow

By Uri Bader, Pierre-Emmanuel Caprace, and Jean Lécureux

Abstract

Let be a locally finite irreducible affine building of dimension , and let be a discrete group acting cocompactly. The goal of this paper is to address the following question: When is linear? More generally, when does admit a finite-dimensional representation with infinite image over a commutative unital ring? If is the Bruhat–Tits building of a simple algebraic group over a local field and if is an arithmetic lattice, then is clearly linear. We prove that if is of type , then the converse holds. In particular, cocompact lattices in exotic -buildings are nonlinear. As an application, we obtain the first infinite family of lattices in exotic -buildings of arbitrarily large thickness, providing a partial answer to a question of W. Kantor from 1986. We also show that if is Bruhat–Tits of arbitrary type, then the linearity of implies that is virtually contained in the linear part of the automorphism group of ; in particular, is an arithmetic lattice. The proofs are based on the machinery of algebraic representations of ergodic systems recently developed by U. Bader and A. Furman. The implementation of that tool in the present context requires the geometric construction of a suitable ergodic -space attached to the the building , which we call the singular Cartan flow.

1. Introduction

1.1. Are lattices in affine buildings linear?

Let be a locally finite affine building with a cocompact automorphism group, and let be a lattice. The goal of this work is to address the following question: When does admit a faithful finite-dimensional linear representations over a field, or more generally over a commutative ring with unity? A group admitting such a representation is called linear.

Let us review some known facts concerning that question.

The most important locally finite affine buildings are the so-called Bruhat–Tits buildings. Such a building is associated with a semisimple algebraic group over a local field . The dimension of coincides with the -rank of . When is -simple, the building is irreducible. In that case, if we assume moreover that , celebrated theorems by Margulis Reference 50 and Venkataramana Reference 78 ensure that lattices in are all arithmetic. It is tempting to deduce that lattices in Bruhat–Tits buildings of dimension  are classified, but this is actually not the case. Indeed, the full automorphism group of the Bruhat–Tits building of is isomorphic to (assuming that the -rank of is ), which is an extension of the group of algebraic automorphisms over by a subgroup (see Reference 13 and Proposition 9.1 below). As long as is infinite—which happens if and only if the local field is of positive characteristic—a lattice in can potentially have infinite image in and, hence, fail to satisfy the hypotheses of the arithmeticity theorem. A lattice in with infinite image in will be called a Galois lattice. Galois lattices exist in rank  (see Proposition 9.4 below), while their existence in higher rank is an open question at the time of writing.

By the seminal work of Tits (see the last corollary in Reference 73), irreducible locally finite affine buildings of dimension  are all Bruhat–Tits buildings of simple algebraic groups over local fields. This is not the case in low dimensions.

If , namely if is a tree with vertex degrees , any uniform lattice in is linear, indeed virtually free. However, a non-uniform lattice can be non-linear.

If and is reducible, then is the product of two trees. In that case Burger and Mozes Reference 16 constructed celebrated examples of uniform lattices that are simple groups, and thus cannot be linear, as they fail to be residually finite. It is still unknown whether an irreducible lattice in a product of more than two topologically simple groups, each acting cocompactly on a tree, can be nonlinear (in this context, the condition of irreducibility means that the projection of the lattice to each simple factor is faithful with dense image).

If and is irreducible, but not Bruhat–Tits, then we say that is exotic. Some of the known constructions of exotic affine buildings and lattices acting on them are referenced in §1.3 below.

The simplest and most studied exotic affine buildings are those of type . They will be of core interest in this paper. Let us recall that (locally finite) -buildings may be characterized among simply connected -dimensional simplicial complexes by the property that the link of every vertex is the incidence graph of a (finite) projective plane; this follows from Reference 29, Th. 7.3. From the classification, it follows that the locally finite Bruhat–Tits buildings of type are precisely those associated with , where is a finite-dimensional division algebra over a local field (see Reference 80, Chapter 28). Thus a locally finite -building is exotic if and only if it is not isomorphic to the Bruhat–Tits building of such a group .

Our first main result, whose proof occupies the major part of this paper, is the following.

Theorem 1.1.

Let be a locally finite -building and be a discrete group acting cocompactly. Assume that is not isomorphic to the building associated to , with a finite-dimensional division algebra over a local field.

Then, for any commutative unital ring and any , any homomorphism has a finite image.

We shall also establish a similar result for Galois lattices in arbitrary Bruhat–Tits buildings of dimension .

Theorem 1.2.

Let be a -simple algebraic group defined over a local field , of -rank . Let be a lattice in .

If has infinite image in , then for any commutative unital ring and any , any homomorphism has a finite image.

Combining the latter theorem with the aforementioned Arithmeticity Theorem, we draw the following consequence.

Corollary 1.3.

Let be the Bruhat–Tits building associated with a -simple algebraic group defined over a local field , of -rank .

A lattice admits a finite-dimensional linear representation with infinite image if and only if is virtually contained (necessarily as an arithmetic subgroup) in the image of in .

In the case of -buildings, we obtain a similar statement without the hypothesis that the ambient building is Bruhat–Tits.

Corollary 1.4.

Let be a locally finite -building and be a discrete group acting cocompactly.

Then admits a representation with infinite image of dimension  over a commutative unital ring if and only if is Bruhat–Tits and is arithmetic.

We mention that by an unpublished work of Yehuda Shalom and Tim Steger we know that every nontrivial normal subgroup of a lattice in an -building is of finite index. Clearly, if the lattice is linear, then finite index normal subgroups are in abundance. The question of finding finite quotients of lattices in possibly exotic affine buildings was already asked by W. Kantor Reference 45, Problem C.6.2. Some computer experiments we held indicate that some nonlinear lattices might have no normal subgroups at all. We suggest the following.

Conjecture 1.5.

Let be a locally finite affine building of type . Assume that is not isomorphic to the building associated to , where is a finite-dimensional division algebra over a local field. Let be a lattice in . Then is virtually simple.

It should be emphasized that, while there are several known constructions of locally finite -buildings with lattices, it is generally a delicate problem to determine whether or not a given such building arising from one of those constructions is Bruhat–Tits. Actually, until very recently, the only examples that could be proved to be exotic are buildings of thickness , and in most cases the proof of exoticity relied on computer calculations. As an application of Theorem 1.1, presented in Section 10, we will establish an exoticity criterion for a large concrete family of -lattices which was first defined by Ronan Reference 60, §3 and Kantor Reference 45, §C.3 and more recently investigated by Essert Reference 35. In particular, we obtain the following.

Corollary 1.6.

Given a power of which is not a power of , there exists an -building of order that is not Bruhat–Tits and admits an automorphism group acting freely and transitively on the set of panels of each type.

This result provides the first infinite family of -lattices in exotic buildings of arbitrarily large thickness, and may be viewed as a partial answer to a question of W. Kantor, who wrote in the remarks following Corollary C.3.2 in Reference 45: “It would be very interesting to know which, if any, of these buildings are “classical” ones obtained from for complete local (skew) fields .” After a first version of this paper was circulated, two more sources of infinite families of -lattices in exotic buildings were found; see Theorem C and Corollary E in Reference 58, and Proposition 7 and Remark 8 in Reference 19.

1.2. Proof ingredients

The proofs of both Theorems 1.1 and 1.2 establish the contrapositive assertion, and thus start by assuming that the lattice has a linear representation with infinite image over a ring.

The first step of the proof is a reduction showing that the given representation can be assumed to have its image contained in a -simple algebraic group over a local field , with an unbounded and Zariski dense image. That step is actually a consequence of an abstract statement of independent interest, valid at a high level of generality, and presented in Appendix A.

At that stage, the proof of Theorem 1.1 reduces to that of the following.

Theorem 1.7.

Let be a locally finite -building and a discrete group consisting of type preserving automorphisms which act cocompactly. Assume that there exist a local field , a connected adjoint -simple -algebraic group , and a group homomorphism with an unbounded and Zariski dense image. Then is a Bruhat–Tits building.

Analogy with Margulis’s Superrigidity Theorem

Our strategy to approach Theorem 1.7 is inspired by the recent proof of the Margulis Superrigidity Theorem by the first author and A. Furman, developed in Reference 5. The tools developed in that work are designed to study a representation of an arbitrary countable group to a -simple algebraic group over a local field , with Zariski dense image. A key notion from Reference 5 is that of a gate (see §8.1 below for more details). This gate is an algebraic variety canonically associated with any standard Borel space equipped with a measure-class preserving ergodic action of . The gate, moreover, provides a natural representation from to a subquotient of the algebraic group , which is nontrivial under suitable assumptions on and .

Therefore, in order to prove Theorem 1.7, we need to provide an ergodic -space such that does not admit any nontrivial representation. The space we shall construct will be called the singular Cartan flow. In order to give a better understanding of its construction, let us first explain what this space is in the “classical” case when is a lattice in , where is a local field.

Let be the subgroup of consisting of diagonal matrices, and let be the singular torus

We consider the -spaces and (or the actions of and on ). Ergodicity is then provided by the Howe–Moore Theorem. The gate of the space gives a representation of .

Geometric analogues in the exotic case.

Now let us go back to the setting of Theorem 1.7, where is a lattice of an -building that is possibly exotic. In particular, the whole group could be discrete, and the -spaces we need to construct can thus hardly be homogeneous spaces of a nondiscrete locally compact enveloping group of . The spaces that we shall construct are of a geometric nature; the measures will be constructed explicitly by hand, and a crucial step in our proof will be to establish their ergodicity.

In order to construct a geometric analogue of the space , we first interpret this space geometrically. The group acts as a group of translations (with compact kernel) on some model apartment of the Bruhat–Tits building associated to . It can be viewed as the stabilizer of this oriented apartment. Hence, is the -orbit of this oriented apartment in , and since acts transitively, is the space of all such apartments. We can also go up one step and consider , equipped with the action of (left multiplication) and (right multiplication). As a dynamical system, this is analogous to the set of simplicial embeddings of the Coxeter complex into , with the action of by postcomposition and the action of by precomposition.

Therefore, in our setting, we are led to consider the set consisting of all simplicial embeddings of the Coxeter complex of type to . The group acts on the set via its action on , while acts on via its action on . In particular, these two actions commute, and we get a -action on the compact space . The latter action is called the Cartan Flow. A measure on is constructed in §§6.2 and 6.4. Its construction will be natural enough so that this measure is invariant under both the action of and the action of .

A geometric analogue of the space from the classical picture is more technical to realize. Let us again describe it first in the classical setting. We want to understand both as a -space and a -space, with both actions commuting. The group acts by translations (with compact kernel) on some singular line . The set of all lines parallel to form a regular tree , which is a so-called panel tree of . This tree is the Bruhat–Tits tree of the Levi subgroup . Hence, an analogue of the -dynamical system is given by a set of embeddings of into . However, since we want the action of to be transitive, we must consider only a -orbit of embeddings. This amounts to ensuring that we embed “as a Bruhat–Tits tree” of .

In the geometric setting, we therefore introduce the space of all embeddings of into our building. It is endowed with an action of (by postcomposition) and (by precomposition with translates of the line ). However, we want to restrict to the analogue of the -orbit. In order to do so, we use the projectivity group of the projective plane at infinity of . That group naturally acts by automorphisms on , and we denote by its closure in (see below for more about this group). We introduce the singular Cartan flow as the orbit of an element by the (commuting) actions of , , and . We again define a natural measure on this space, which takes into account both the geometric measure on and the Haar measure on (see §6.3 for more details).

Ergodicity results

A fundamental step in our proof of Theorem 1.7 is the following (see Theorems 7.1 and 7.3 for more precise statements).

Theorem 1.8.

The Cartan flow and the singular Cartan flow are ergodic.

As mentioned above, those flows are a not necessarily homogeneous space of some locally compact groups; in particular, the ergodicity cannot be deduced from the Howe–Moore Theorem as is done in the classical picture. The relevant tool happens to be the one originally used in the study of the geodesic flow on manifolds with variable negative curvature, namely Hopf’s argument Reference 41 (see also Reference 32 for a nice introduction). In Appendix B we give an abstract version of the Hopf argument which is suited for our purpose. The Cartan flow is not needed for the end of the proof, but it is an intermediate step in the proof of the ergodicity of the singular Cartan flow.

If denotes the singular Cartan flow, the gate theory provides us with a linear representation of (the latter group is in the classical case). It follows from the construction of the singular Cartan flow that the group naturally contains the group introduced above, which is the closure of the natural image in of the projectivity group of the projective plane at infinity of . This projectivity group has a lot more structure than : it acts on a locally finite tree (a so-called panel tree of ) with a -transitive action on its boundary. The final step in the proof of Theorem 1.7 will be deduced from the following result of independent interest (see Theorem 4.7).

Theorem 1.9.

Let be a locally finite -building and be the closure of the projectivity group in the locally compact group . If an open subgroup of admits a faithful continuous representation , where is a local field, then is a Bruhat–Tits building.

It should be emphasized that, while all the other steps of the proof generalize with only small modifications to Euclidean buildings of types other than , we do not know how to extend Theorem 1.9 to or buildings. Indeed, the proof of the latter relies on a result on projective planes due to A. Schleiermarcher (Theorem 3.2), whose analogue for generalized quadrangles and generalized hexagons is still unknown. In this regard, we make the following remark.

Remark 1.10.

Let be a locally finite 2-dimensional affine building, and let be a discrete cocompact group of isometries of . Let be the closure of the projectivity group of in the locally compact group . By the methods of our proof of Theorem 1.1 below, one could show that if is non-linear then also is non-linear. While we do not know in general that is nonlinear for exotic locally finite buildings of type or , given a concrete example of such a building it might be possible to check the nonlinearity of directly. For example, in the panel-regular exotic buildings of type considered in Reference 44 and Reference 35, some of the residues are nonclassical finite generalized quadrangles of order for a prime power . In the case where , it would suffice to check that the projectivity groups of those quadrangles contain the full alternating group to ensure that the closure of the projectivity group in the automorphism group of the panel tree is locally symmetric or alternating, hence nonlinear as a consequence of the main results from Reference 56.

Let us now briefly discuss the proof of Theorem 1.2, which is presented in Section 9. It also relies on the Bader–Furman machinery from Reference 5. The starting point of that proof is the observation that the argument for Theorem 1.1 sketched above also provides relevant information when is the Bruhat–Tits building of . Indeed, while in that case the projectivity group is isomorphic to , and is thus linear by hypothesis, it turns out that the group of automorphisms of the Cartan flow commuting with considered above can be strictly larger than the projectivity group. More precisely, if is a Galois lattice, then has an infinite (hence nonvirtually abelian by property (T)) image in the quotient , which is virtually the group of field automorphisms of . It then turns out that is also a nonabelian group of field automorphisms of . On the other hand, the gate theory provides us with a continuous faithful representation of the locally compact group , and by the general structure theory of linear locally compact groups from Reference 25, this implies that must in fact be virtually abelian. This shows that if is linear, then it cannot be a Galois lattice. This part of the argument does not require to be of type , and is actually valid for arbitrary irreducible Bruhat–Tits buildings of dimension . Indeed the relevant -spaces are homogeneous spaces of the nondiscrete group , and their ergodicity can be established by a suitable application of the Howe–Moore Theorem.

1.3. A review of exotic -dimensional buildings with lattices

The aforementioned classification of irreducible affine buildings of dimension  was completed in the early days of the 1980s. The existence of exotic -dimensional affine buildings came soon after. Some of them have no nontrivial automorphisms whatsoever (see, e.g., Reference 61); this is, in particular, the case of generic -buildings (in a suitably defined Baire categorical sense); see Reference 8, Th. 5. Some have a cocompact automorphism group, with a global fixed vertex at infinity; see Reference 77, §7. The existence of such a fixed point prevents that group from being unimodular (see Reference 22, Th. M), and hence cannot contain any lattice. The known exotic -buildings relevant to Theorem 1.1 are those endowed with a proper cocompact action of a discrete group. They are constructed as universal covers of finite simple complexes having finite projective planes as residues, or of suitably defined finite complexes of groups. The constructions that we are aware of are the following (the order of a locally finite -building is the common order of its residue planes, i.e., the finite projective planes appearing as its rank  residues).

In Reference 75, §3.1 and Reference 60, Th. 2.5, Tits and Ronan construct four -buildings of order  with cocompact lattices. The lattices act regularly (i.e., sharply transitively) on the set of chambers of their building. It is shown in Reference 74, §3.1 and Reference 48 that two of those are Bruhat–Tits buildings with arithmetic lattices, while the other two are exotic (see also Reference 45, §3.6).

In Reference 75, §3.1 and Reference 74, §3.2, Tits constructs 44 buildings of type , of order , with cocompact lattices acting regularly on the set of chambers of their building. It is asserted that 43 of them are exotic.

In Reference 60, §3 and Reference 45, §C.3, Ronan and Kantor describe a framework providing, in particular, cocompact lattices of -buildings acting regularly on the panels of each given type. Such lattices are called panel-regular.

In Reference 27, Cartwright–Mantero–Steger–Zappa construct exotic -buildings of order with cocompact lattices. In those examples, the lattices act regularly on the set of vertices of their builing; in particular, the types of vertices are permuted cyclically.

In Reference 7, §3, Barré constructs an exotic -building of order with a cocompact lattice. The full automorphism group of that building is discrete and has exactly two orbits of vertices.

In Reference 35, Essert provides presentations of arbitrary panel-regular lattices in -buildings. When the building is of order , there are exactly two inequivalent presentations of such groups. One of them gives rise to an arithmetic group, the other is exotic (see Remark 10.8 and Lemma 10.9 below). The -buildings of order  and admitting a panel-regular lattice have recently been classified by S. Witzel (see Reference 81), who determined which are exotic and described their full automorphism group. We show in Section 10 how to use Theorem 1.1 to establish Corollary 1.6 and, more generally, to construct, from a given panel-regular lattice in an exotic of order , an infinite family of panel-regular lattices in an exotic -building of order .

In all of the previous examples, the residue planes are always Desarguesian. Recently, N. Radu Reference 57 constructed an example of an exotic -building of order , with a vertex-transitive, virtually torsion-free, discrete automorphism group and with non-Desarguesian residues (isomorphic to the Hughes plane of order ).

After the first version of the present paper was circulated, two more sources of exotic -buildings with lattices were identified:

In Proposition 7 and Remark 8 in Reference 19, it is shown that for every non-Desarguesian finite projection plane , there is a locally finite -building with a discrete group acting cocompactly such that has a residue plane isomorphic to . In particular, must be exotic. Since there exist non-Desarguesian finite projective planes of arbitrarily large order, this provides another infinite family of lattices in exotic -buildings of unbounded order. It is not known whether the lattices constructed in this way are virtually torsion-free.

In Theorem C and Corollary E in Reference 58, it is proved that, among the panel-regular lattices in -buildings studied by Essert and mentioned above, the proportion of the exotic ones tends (exponentially fast) to as the order of the building tends to infinity. In particular, it follows from Theorem 1.1 that the “vast majority” of panel-regular lattices in -buildings considered by Essert are nonlinear.

Remark that in all those examples, the lattices are cocompact: no exotic example with a nonuniform lattice is known.

Exotic buildings of type and have been less investigated, but some constructions are known; see Reference 44 and Reference 35. In fact, the most fascinating example of an exotic -dimensional affine building with a cocompact lattice is probably the building of type constructed by Kantor Reference 44 as the universal cover of a simplicial complex associated with the finite sporadic simple group of Lyons (see also Reference 74, §3.5). The corresponding building is exotic (an assertion attributed to Tits, without proof, in Reference 44). This can be deduced from the fact that the full automorphism group of that building is discrete, a fact established by Grüninger Reference 40, Cor. 3.3.

1.4. Structure of the paper

The next two sections are of an introductory nature and review known material. The next section, §2, serves as a concise introduction to -buildings. In particular, we recall the notions of wall trees and panel trees, which are of great importance in this work. In §3 we recall the notion of the projectivity group and explain how it acts on panel trees. In subsection §3.3 we discuss linear representations and algebraicity of groups acting on trees. In §4 we use the results of the previous section in order to study linear representations of the projectivity group. The main result of this section is Theorem 4.7, which roughly states that the projectivity group of a building admits a linear representation if and only if the building is Bruhat–Tits. This result may be of independent interest. The proof of Theorem 1.7 will be carried eventually by a reduction to this theorem.

The next three sections, §§5, 6, and 7 are devoted to the construction and the study of some new spaces, the most important of which are the the space of marked flats and space of (restricted) marked wall trees. We define these as topological spaces in §5 and introduce their measured structure in §6. Finally, in §7, we prove ergodicity results for these spaces. The ergodicity of the singular Cartan flow, Theorem 7.3, is the technical heart of this paper.

In §8 we combine Theorem 7.3 with the theory of algebraic gates in order to reduce the proof of Theorem 1.7 to Theorem 4.7. We then proceed and prove Theorem 1.1.

The last two sections contain supplementary results. In §9 we consider Galois lattices. The goal of that section is to establish Theorem 1.2. Finally, in §10, we use the results of the paper to construct a concrete infinite family of exotic -lattices, a result recorded in Corollary 1.6.

The paper has two appendices. They contain essential ingredients in the proof of the main theorems of the paper, which are presented as appendices due to their independent characters. The first is Appendix A, which is devoted to the proof of Theorem A.1. This theorem is the main ingredient in the reduction of Theorem 1.1 to Theorem 1.7. In Appendix B we review the classical Hopf argument in an abstract setting. In particular, we prove Theorem B.1, which is essential in the proofs given in §7.

2. -buildings and their boundaries

In this section we recall some basic facts on -buildings and their boundaries. In §2.1 we give a general introduction to -buildings and in §2.2 we discuss their boundaries. In §2.3 we discuss the important notions of wall trees and panel trees. Most of the results we will state here are well known, and we will not provide proofs in these cases. Standard references on the subject are Reference 2, Reference 37 and Reference 62.

2.1. Buildings of type

Let us start by recalling the definition of a building of type (or -building for short). We denote by a model apartment: it is the -dimensional simplicial complex afforded by the tessellation of the Euclidean plane by equilateral triangles. A wall in is a line in which is a union of edges. We fix a vertex .

Definition 2.1.

A building of type is a triangular complex satisfying the following two conditions, in which we call an apartment a subcomplex of isomorphic to :

Any two simplices of are contained in an apartment.

If and are two apartments, there exists a simplicial isomorphism which fixes pointwise .

The -dimensional simplices of an -building are called chambers. The space is endowed with a natural metric, defined as follows: the distance between two points and is the distance between and calculated in any apartment containing and . This is well-defined, and furthermore gives a CAT(0) metric on . Apartments are also called flats, because in the CAT()-metric on , the apartments are maximal subspaces isometric to a Euclidean space.

An -building is equipped with a coloring of its vertex set such that each chamber has exactly one vertex of each color. The color of a vertex is called its type.

We assume throughout that the building is thick, i.e., there are more than two chambers adjacent to each edge.

It is worth noting that the local geometry is forced by the geometry of the building. For a start, the building is regular: the cardinality of the set of chambers adjacent to an edge is constant (see for example Reference 52, Theorem 2.4). When that number is finite, we define the order of the -building as the number such that the number of chambers adjacent to each edge equals . Since we assumed to be thick, we have .

Furthermore, the link at a vertex is always a finite projective plane, and the boundary of the building is a compact (profinite) projective plane. For the convenience of the reader, we recall the definition.⁠Footnote1

1

Strictly speaking, the definition we give is the definition of the incidence graph of a projective plane; the identification of a projective plane and its incidence graph, implicit throughout this paper, should not cause any confusion.

Definition 2.2.

A projective plane is a bipartite graph, with two types of vertices (called points and lines) such that:

Any two lines are adjacent to a unique point.

Any two points are adjacent to a unique line.

There exist four points, no three of which are adjacent to a common line.

Projective planes are also known as generalized triangles, or thick buildings of type .

Another striking feature of - (or more general affine) buildings is the following fact.

Theorem 2.3.

Let be a subset of which is either convex or of nonempty interior. If is isometric to a subset of , then there exists an apartment such that .

An important class of subsets of to which we will apply this theorem is the following.

Definition 2.4.

A sector based at in is a connected component of the complement in of the union of the walls passing through .

A sector of is a subset of which is isometric to a sector in .

2.2. Boundaries of buildings

Let be a building of type . Although we shall primarily view as a -dimensional simplicial complex, we will occasionally refer to as a CAT() metric space. Such a metric realization is obtained by giving each of length , and endowing each -simplex with the metric of a Euclidean equilateral triangle with side length . Since is a CAT() space, its ideal boundary is naturally endowed with the structure of a CAT() space. The combinatorial nature of is such that inherits a much finer structure, namely that of a compact projective plane, equipped with a family of natural measures.

2.2.1. The projective plane at infinity

A boundary point is called a vertex at infinity if it is the endpoint of a geodesic ray parallel to a wall in . Two sectors and in are equivalent if their intersection contains a sector; equivalently, their ideal boundaries and coincide. An equivalence class of sectors (or, equivalently, the ideal boundary of a sector) is called a Weyl chamber.

Two Weyl chambers are called adjacent if they contain a common vertex at infinity. This happens if and only if they are represented by two sectors whose intersection contains a geodesic ray. We let denote the graph whose vertices are the vertices at infinity such that two vertices define an edge if the corresponding vertices at infinity lie in a common Weyl chamber. The set of edges of is denoted by . The ideal boundary may be viewed as a CAT() metric realization of the graph .

We can finally state the fact alluded to above.

Theorem 2.5.

The graph is a projective plane.

A key point in the proof of this theorem is to prove that two chambers are always in some apartment at infinity. An intermediate step is the following lemma, which is also useful to us.

Lemma 2.6.

Let be a vertex in , and . There exists a unique sector based at in the equivalence class of . We denote this sector by .

Two chambers in are called opposite if they are at maximal distance (i.e., at distance three). Similarly, two vertices are called opposite if they are at maximal distance.

By convexity of apartments, the convex hull of two chambers is contained in any apartment containing both of them. This explains the following.

Lemma 2.7.

Two opposite chambers are contained in a unique apartment.

We note for further use the following standard fact Reference 79, Proposition 29.50.

Lemma 2.8.

For every pair of chambers , there exists a chamber which is opposite to both and .

2.2.2. Topology on

The projective plane , seen as the boundary of , is endowed with a natural topology: indeed, is naturally endowed with the structure of a compact projective plane. One way to topologize consists of observing that the ideal boundary with its natural metric is a metric realization of the graph , so that a vertex of is a point in and an edge of is a geodesic segment in . Moreover, the vertex-set of is a closed subset of the ideal boundary endowed with the cone topology. Thus the vertex-set of inherits a compact topology from the cone topology on . Similarly, the edge-set of , denoted by , can be topologized via the map that sends each edge of to its midpoint in . In that way the vertex-set and edge-set of are naturally endowed with a topology that is compact and totally disconnected (see Reference 23, Prop. 3.5). A basis of open sets of the topology on is provided by the sets of the form , where and are vertices of .

We note the following fact for further use.

Lemma 2.9.

Let be a chamber. The set of chambers which are opposite to is an open subset of .

Proof.

Fix an apartment containing , and let be the chamber in opposite to . Let be the set of chambers opposite to . Then is the union of sets of the form , where is a vertex in and is a vertex in the sector .

2.3. Wall trees and panel trees

Important tools in our study of triangular buildings are wall trees and panel trees. These closely related notions were introduced by Tits in his study of the structure and classification of affine buildings. A good reference is Reference 80, Chapters 10 and 11.

Let us start by defining wall trees. These trees are defined as equivalence classes of parallel lines. A geodesic line is said to be singular if it is parallel to a wall in some (hence any) apartment containing it; otherwise it is called regular.

Definition 2.10.

Two geodesic lines and are called parallel if they are contained in a common apartment, and are parallel in this apartment. The distance between parallel lines is the Euclidean distance between them in any apartment containing them.

Parallelism is an equivalence relation. Furthermore, the distance between parallel lines turns each class into a metric space.

For regular lines, this space is just isometric to . However, these spaces turn out to be interesting for singular lines Reference 80, Proposition 10.14 and Corollary 10.16.

Proposition 2.11.

Let be a singular line, and be the set of lines parallel to . Then is a thick tree. If is locally finite of order , then is regular of degree .

The tree defined above is called a wall tree. Note that every geodesic line parallel to has the same two endpoints at infinity as . These two endpoints are by definition vertices (or panels) of the building at infinity .

Now we turn to the definition of a panel tree. Let be a vertex of . Then is represented by an equivalence class of geodesic rays, two of them being equivalent if they contain subrays that are contained in a common apartment and are parallel in that apartment.

Definition 2.12.

Two geodesic rays are said to be asymptotic if their intersection contains a ray.

If two rays belong to the same equivalence class, their distance is defined as

It is clear that this distance only depends on the asymptotic classes of and . It is possible to check that we indeed have a distance on the set of asymptotic classes of rays in the class of .

Proposition 2.13.

The metric space, denoted , of asymptotic classes of rays in the class of , is a thick tree. If is locally finite of order , then is regular of degree .

This proposition can be found in Reference 80, Corollary 11.18. The tree is called the panel tree associated to .

Panel trees are related to wall trees via canonical maps Reference 80, Proposition 11.16.

Proposition 2.14.

Let be a singular geodesic line, and be an endpoint of . Then the map which associates to a line parallel to its asymptotic class is an isometry.

The set of ends of a panel tree is also well understood. Any ray in can be lifted to a sequence of adjacent parallel geodesic rays in some apartment containing . To such a sequence one can associate the chamber, in the boundary of , which contains and goes in the direction of the sequence of rays. This explains the construction of the bijection in the following proposition Reference 80, Proposition 11.22.

Proposition 2.15.

Let be a vertex in . There is a canonical -equivariant bijection between the set of ends of the panel tree and the set of chambers of containing .

3. Structure of the projectivity group

The projectivity group is an important invariant of the building at infinity , and plays a crucial role in our proofs. In this chapter we define it and discuss its properties. In the next section, §4, we will study its linear representations. First, in §3.1 we define the projectivity group in the context of a general projective plane, and then, in §3.2, in the restricted setting of an affine building. In the latter setting, we will explain how the projectivity group acts on a panel tree. The last subsection, §3.3, is devoted to the general study of linear representations of groups acting on trees. This is a preparation for §4.

3.1. Projectivity groups of projective planes

In this section, we recall some basic terminology on projectivity groups and record important known results that will be needed in what follows.

Let be a thick building of type (i.e., is a projective plane). If is a vertex of , we denote by the set of chambers of adjacent to .

Let and be opposite vertices of . The combinatorial projection to is the map from to which associates to the unique chamber of which is at minimal distance from . The fact that we chose and opposite implies that this projection, restricted to , is an involutory bijection.

Given a sequence of vertices such that is opposite and for all , we obtain a bijection of to by composing the successive projection maps from to . That bijection is called a perspectivity; it is denoted by . In the special case when , it is called a projectivity at . The collection of all projectivities at a vertex is denoted by ; it is a permutation group of the set , called the projectivity group of at and denoted by . The isomorphism type of the permutation group does not depend on the choice of the vertex . Indeed, given another vertex , there exists a perspectivity from to (because is thick; see Lemma 2.8), which conjugates onto . For that reason, it makes sense to define the projectivity group of the building as any representative of the isomorphism class of the projectivity group at a vertex .

Proposition 3.1.

The projectivity group of a thick building of type is -transitive.

Proof.

See Proposition 2.4 in Reference 17.

We remark that projectivity groups can be defined for arbitrary generalized polygons; a result of N. Knarr Reference 46, Lemma 1.2 ensures that they are always -transitive.

The projectivity group is an important invariant of a projective plane . For example, it is known that is sharply -transitive if and only if is a projective plane over a commutative field; see Theorem 2.5 in Reference 17. We will need an important variant of that fact. In order to state it, we recall that a -transitive permutation group is called a Moufang set if there exists a set of subgroups of such that for each , the group acts sharply transitively on and for all . The subgroups for are called the root groups of the Moufang set.

Theorem 3.2.

Let be a thick building of type . Then is Moufang if and only if the projectivity group is a Moufang set.

Proof.

See the main result from Reference 64.

We will also need the following elementary criterion, ensuring that a projectivity of a very specific form is nontrivial.

Lemma 3.3.

Let be a thick building of type . Let be chambers such that is a half-apartment of for all .

For all , let be the vertex of that is not contained in . If and , then the projectivity is nontrivial; indeed, its only fixed point in is .

Proof.

Observe first that the projectivity fixes . Let be any chamber different from . We claim that does not fix . Indeed, we define inductively, for each , the chamber as the projection of to , and as the unique chamber which is adjacent to both and . It then follows that for all , the chamber is adjacent to . Moreover, is adjacent to .

By definition, we have . Therefore, if , then is adjacent to so that forms a closed gallery of length . Therefore, we must have or , which forces, respectively, or .

3.2. Projectivity groups of Euclidean buildings

Now, let us go back to the situation when is a thick Euclidean building of type , and is the set of chambers of its building at infinity. In that particular case, the projectivity group of is more than just a permutation group of a set . Indeed, to each vertex , one associates the panel tree , as in Proposition 2.13.

Let and be two opposite vertices of different types in , and let be a geodesic line in joining these two vertices. By Proposition 2.14, the panel trees and are both canonically isomorphic to the wall tree . Hence we have a canonical involutory isomorphism between the panel trees and .

From that observation, it follows that any perspectivity of to defines an isomorphism of panel trees from to , and that the projectivity group at acts by automorphisms on the panel tree . We define the projectivity group of at as by viewing the usual projectivity group as a subgroup of . Thus the projectivity group of at is , since the set is canonically isomorphic to the set of ends of the panel tree by Proposition 2.15. Note that by using isomorphisms as described above, all wall trees and all panel trees are mutually isomorphic (though not canonically).

Definition 3.4.

We fix once and for all a tree which is isomorphic to all panel and wall trees in and call it the model tree of . By choosing an actual identification of with a panel tree and pulling back the projectivity group , we define , the model projectivity group of .

Lemma 3.5.

The projectivity group acts -transitively on and acts vertex-transitively on . In particular, is regular. If, moreover, is locally finite of order , then is locally finite of degree .

Proof.

The -transitivity of on follows from Proposition 3.1. is vertex-transitive on , since every vertex can be uniquely determined by a triple of distinct ends. The regularity of follows. The last assertion follows from Propositions 2.11 and 2.14.

3.3. Algebraic groups and locally finite trees

In this section we recall some general results on groups acting on trees that we need in our analysis of the group of projectivities of an -building.

3.3.1. Linear simple locally compact groups are algebraic

A locally compact group is called linear if it has a continuous, faithful, finite-dimensional representation over a locally compact field.

Theorem 3.6.

Let be a t.d.l.c. group such that the intersection of all nontrivial closed normal subgroups of is compactly generated, topologically simple and nondiscrete, and that the quotient is compact. If has a linear open subgroup, then the following assertions hold:

(i)

is algebraic: indeed, is isomorphic to , where is a local field, is an absolutely simple, simply connected algebraic group defined and isotropic over , and is the center of .

(ii)

is virtually abelian.

Proof.

Assertion (i) follows from Corollary 1.4 from Reference 25. Assertion (ii) follows from Theorem 1.1 in Reference 25 and the fact that the compact open subgroups of are not solvable (indeed they are Zariski-dense in a simple algebraic group).

3.3.2. Boundary-transitive automorphism groups of trees

The following result, due to Burger–Mozes Reference 15, provides a natural set-up where all hypotheses of Theorem 3.6 other than the linearity are satisfied.

Theorem 3.7.

Let be a thick locally finite tree and be a closed subgroup acting -transitively on the set of ends .

Then the intersection of all nontrivial closed normal subgroups of is compactly generated, topologically simple, and nondiscrete. It acts edge-transitively on and -transitively on , and the quotient is compact. In particular, is unimodular.

Proof.

See Proposition 3.1.2 from Reference 15 and Theorem 2.2 from Reference 21. For the unimodularity of , observe that must be in the kernel of the modular character of . Thus the modular character of factors through the quotient , which is compact. Hence is indeed unimodular.

An automorphism of a tree is called horocyclic if it fixes pointwise a horosphere of . Combining the previous two statements, we obtain a subsidiary result which is a key tool in the proof of our characterization.

Proposition 3.8.

Let be a thick locally finite tree and be a closed subgroup acting -transitively on the set of ends . If has a linear open subgroup, then the following assertions hold:

(i)

The group , defined as in Theorem 3.7, is isomorphic to , where is a local field, is an absolutely simple, simply connected algebraic -group of -rank , and is the center of .

(ii)

is a Moufang set whose root groups are the unipotent radicals of proper -parabolic subgroups of .

(iii)

Each element which is a horocyclic automorphism of belongs to some root group.

(iv)

The quotient is virtually abelian.

Proof.

By Theorems 3.6 and 3.7, we know that , defined as in Theorem 3.7, is isomorphic to , where is a local field and is an absolutely simple, simply connected algebraic -group of -rank . Since acts properly and cocompactly on a thick locally finite tree, its -rank must be  (see for example Reference 69, Corollary 4). This proves (i).

It is well known, and easy to see using maximal compact subgroups, that has, up to isomorphism, a unique continuous proper cocompact action by automorphisms on a thick locally finite tree (see, e.g., Lemma 2.6(viii) from Reference 20 for a proof). Thus is isomorphic to the Bruhat–Tits tree of . It follows that is a Moufang set whose root groups are the unipotent radicals of proper -parabolic subgroups of . Since is normal in , it follows that the root groups are permuted by conjugation under . Therefore, the permutation group is also a Moufang set. This proves (ii).

In order to establish (iii), we recall that the contraction group of an element is defined as

Now let be a horocyclic element, and let be the center of the horosphere of fixed by . Given any hyperbolic element whose repelling fixed point is , we have . We can choose such a hyperbolic in (this is possible because is -transitive on ). The image of in the compact quotient must be trivial, so that . We now invoke Reference 55, Lemma 2.4, ensuring that is a root group of the Moufang set . This proves (iii). The assertion (iv) holds by Theorems 3.6(ii) and 3.7.

4. Structure and representations of the group of projectivities

The goal of this section is to prove Theorem 4.7 which roughly states that the projectivity group is linear if and only if the building is a Bruhat–Tits building. The proof of this theorem will be carried in §4.2. It relies on Proposition 4.1 below, whose proof is our main concern in §4.1.

4.1. Existence of horocyclic elements

This subsection is devoted to the proof of the following technical result.

Proposition 4.1.

Let be a thick Euclidean building of type . Then the projectivity group contains a nontrivial horocyclic automorphism of the panel tree defined in Definition 3.4.

We need to collect a number of subsidiary facts, assuming throughout that is a thick Euclidean building of type whose projective plane at infinity is denoted by . The proof of Proposition 4.1 is deferred to the end of the section.

Lemma 4.2.

Let be vertices of , and be geodesic lines such that the two endpoints of the line are and for all , where the indices are written modulo .

If is nonempty for all modulo , then the projectivity fixes the point of the panel tree represented by .

Proof.

Let be the point represented by . Its image under the projectivity is the point of represented by . Since the intersection is nonempty, it contains a geodesic ray tending to . Thus fixes as claimed.

Lemma 4.3.

Let be vertices of , and be geodesic lines with such that the two endpoints of the line are and for .

Let be the point represented by . Suppose that is a vertex of , and let be a vertex adjacent to . Let be the geodesic line parallel to and representing . Also let be the geodesic line parallel to and representing the same point of as .

Let be a chamber of with vertices . If and are both contained in and if is contained in , then .

Proof.

We refer to Figure 1. Upon exchanging and , we can assume that belongs to the geodesic ray . Therefore also belongs to the geodesic ray since .

Let (resp., ) be the first vertex different from on the geodesic ray (resp., ). We claim that is opposite in the residue of the vertex .

To establish the claim, we first observe that is adjacent to . Indeed, by hypothesis the first vertex different from on the geodesic segment is . Since the line is singular, it is a wall in any apartment that contains it. Since the chamber has a panel on , we may find an apartment containing both the line and the chamber . In particular, that apartment contains the geodesic rays and , which are parallel. It follows that is adjacent to , as desired. Similarly, is adjacent to .

This observation implies that the vertices and have the same type. Hence and have different types. Therefore, if and are not opposite in , then they are adjacent. But the unique vertex in which is adjacent to both and is . Thus, if the claim fails, then we have . This implies that the first vertex different from on is . Therefore the first vertex different from on is opposite in . On the other hand, as seen above, the first vertex different from on is . Thus is opposite in . This is absurd since is adjacent to . The claim is established.

The claim implies that the union of the geodesic rays is a geodesic line intersecting in the geodesic ray . Therefore that line must coincide with , which confirms that .

Lemma 4.4.

Let be vertices of , and be geodesic lines such that two endpoints of the line are and for all .

Suppose that the point represented by is a vertex and let be a vertex adjacent to . Let be the geodesic line parallel to and representing . For , inductively define as the geodesic line parallel to and representing the same point of as .

For each , if is a geodesic segment of length , then is a geodesic segment of length .

Proof.

Since the line represents a vertex of , it lies on the boundary of a half-apartment, and thus entirely consists of vertices and edges of . Let be the geodesic segment (where is a vertex) which is the intersection so that by hypothesis.

For all , let be the unique vertex belonging to which is adjacent to both and . By invoking Lemma 4.3 three times successively, we see that is contained in , , and . This proves that the segment , which is of length , is contained in .

Lemma 4.5.

Let be vertices, and be geodesic lines such that two endpoints of the line are and for all . Suppose that the point represented by is a vertex.

If is a geodesic segment of length , then the projectivity fixes the ball of radius around pointwise.

Proof.

Let be a vertex at distance  from . Let be the geodesic line parallel to and representing . For , inductively define as the geodesic line parallel to and representing the same point of as .

An immediate induction on , using Lemma 4.4, shows that is a geodesic segment of length . By Lemma 4.2, this implies that is fixed by .

Lemma 4.6.

Let be a vertex. Let be sectors based at such that is a half-apartment of for all . For all , let be the boundary line of , and let be the common endpoint of and .

Then the projectivity is a horocyclic automorphism of the tree .

Proof.

We refer to Figure 2.

Let be the vertex represented by , and let be the geodesic ray of represented by the sector .

We claim that the projectivity fixes the ball of radius around pointwise so that is indeed horocyclic.

To see this, let be the geodesic line parallel to and representing . For , inductively define as the geodesic line parallel to and representing the same point of as .

By construction, the line is contained in the half-apartment . Therefore, it intersects the sector in a segment of length . In particular, the intersection is a geodesic segment of length . The claim then follows from Lemma 4.5.

Proof of Proposition 4.1.

Let be a vertex. Let be sectors based at such that is a half-apartment of for all . Since is thick, we may choose those sectors such that is a geodesic ray, for all . In particular, denoting the boundary chamber of by , we have and .

For all , let be the boundary line of , and let be the common endpoint of and .

By Lemma 4.6, the projectivity is a horocyclic automorphism of the tree . By Lemma 3.3, the projectivity is a nontrivial permutation of so that is indeed a nontrivial automorphism of .

4.2. -buildings with a linear projectivity group are Bruhat–Tits

Theorem 4.7.

Let be a thick, locally finite, Euclidean building of type . Let be its projectivity group, viewed as a subgroup of , where is the model tree of . Let, moreover, denote the closure of in the group endowed with the compact-open topology.

If has an open subgroup admitting a continuous, faithful, finite-dimensional representation over a local field, then is a Bruhat–Tits building.

By the classification of Bruhat–Tits buildings, one knows that is then the Euclidean building associated with , where is a finite-dimensional division algebra over a local field (see Reference 80, Chapter 28). Notice, moreover, that the converse to Theorem 4.7 holds: indeed, if is the Euclidean building associated with , then its projectivity group is acting on its Bruhat–Tits tree (this follows from Proposition 2.3 from Reference 46).

Proof of Theorem 4.7.

By Proposition 3.1, the projectivity group is -transitive. In particular is -transitive on . We may therefore invoke Proposition 3.8, which ensures that is a Moufang set.

By Proposition 4.1, the group contains a nontrivial element which is a horocyclic automorphism of . By Proposition 3.8(iii), that element belongs to a root group of , for some end . Since is Moufang, it follows that is normal in . In particular is normal in . Since is -transitive on , it follows that is -transitive on , and hence any nontrivial normal subgroup of is transitive on . We have seen that is a nontrivial normal subgroup of and is thus transitive on . Since the root group is sharply transitive on , we must have . It follows that is a Moufang set. Therefore the building at infinity is Moufang by Theorem 3.2. Equivalently is Bruhat–Tits.

5. Other topological spaces associated with -buildings

Throughout this section, we let be a locally finite -building and let be a discrete subgroup consisting of type-preserving automorphisms which acts cocompactly on . The goal of this section is to define auxiliary topological spaces associated with the pair and needed for subsequent developments. In particular, in §5.1 we define the space consisting of marked flats and in §5.2 the space consisting of marked wall trees. It turns out that the space is too big for our purposes. We therefore define the notion of restricted marked wall trees and study the space of such objects in §5.3. Unfortunately, this makes our discussion a bit technical. With the hope of helping the reader overcome those technicalities, we provide in §5.4 a broad overview of the spaces we consider and the maps connecting them.

5.1. The space of marked flats

We fix a model flat for , a base vertex , and a sector based at . The direction of is called the positive Weyl chamber. The sector of based at and opposite is denoted by . We let be the group of simplicial translations of (not necessarily type-preserving). The group acts sharply transitively on the vertices of . We let be the group of type-preserving automorphisms of fixing . It is called the (spherical) Weyl group of and is isomorphic to the symmetric group .

Definition 5.1.

A marked flat in is a simplicial (not necessarily type-preserving) embedding . We denote by the set of marked flats in and endow it with the topology of pointwise convergence.

Remark 5.2.

By Theorem 2.3 the image of a marked flat in is indeed a flat in .

Note that is locally compact as is locally finite. In fact it is easy to see how is decomposed into a disjoint union of compact open subspaces. We define a map

where as before denotes the vertex-set of . For each we let denote the preimage of under this map. Clearly the subsets are compact open and .

The group acts on by precomposition and acts on by postcomposition. Thus these two actions commute. We endow and with the quotient topologies. Note that is a -space and is a -space.

Lemma 5.3.

The space is a compact -space.

Proof.

The union of the spaces taken over a finite set of representatives of the -orbits in is compact and maps surjectively onto . The latter is thus indeed compact.

Recall that two chambers in are called opposite if they are at maximal distance in the graph (i.e., at distance 3). We denote by the set of ordered pairs of opposite chambers, and endow it with the topology induced by the product topology. This is a locally compact topology. We consider the map

where denotes the equivalence class of the sector which is a chamber in and similarly for which is an opposite chamber.

Lemma 5.4.

The map induces a -equivariant homeomorphism between and .

Proof.

We first check that is continuous. Assume that are embeddings of converging to . Then there exists such that for large enough we have , and for even larger , is constant on the ball of radius around . In particular, and are in for some at distance from (see Section 2.2.2 for the definition of the set ). Hence converges to , and similarly for .

By Lemma 2.7, is surjective and its fibers are exactly the -orbits on since is vertex-transitive on . By the definition of the quotient topology we thus obtain a continuous bijection . We need to show that is an open map. For we denote by the image of in . Note that is an open cover of . Thus it is enough to show that is open. By compactness, is a homeomorphism of onto its image, thus it is enough to show that has an open image. Note that is the union of all , where the vertices and have the following properties: the geodesic segment contains , and is not contained in any wall of any apartment in . Hence this set is indeed open in .

5.2. The space of marked wall trees

A flat in may be viewed as the union of all geodesic lines that are parallel to a given regular line in (see Section 2.3 for the definition of regular and singular lines). We now develop analogous notions for the case of a singular line. Let be a singular geodesic line in so that the two endpoints of are vertices of . The union of all geodesic lines in that are parallel to is a closed CAT()-convex subset of . As a CAT() space, it is isometric to the product , where is the wall tree associated to (see Proposition 2.11). In particular, is isomorphic to the model tree (see Definition 3.4). Conversely, using Theorem 2.3 it is not hard to see that any isometric embedding of the CAT() space in arises in that way.

The subspace also inherits a simplicial structure from . We shall now describe that simplicial structure abstractly. The model wall tree of is the simplicial complex denoted by and defined as follows. Fix a base vertex in the model tree of . The vertex set of is the collection of pairs , where is a vertex of and is a real number that satisfies the following conditions: if the distance is even, then , while if is odd, then . Two distinct vertices, and , form an edge of if and only if and . The -simplices of are defined so that every triple of distinct vertices that are pairwise adjacent are contained in a unique -simplex. This defines the model wall tree as a simplicial complex.

Let us mention that a CAT() metric realization of is obtained by giving each edge length and by endowing each -simplex with the metric of a Euclidean equilateral triangle. In that way carries a complete CAT() metric that is isometric to , where is viewed as a metric tree in which edges have length . That isometry is the identity on the vertex set , which has been defined as a subset of . Although we shall not need that fact, let us mention moreover that every simplicial embedding is also an isometric embedding with respect to the respective CAT() metric realizations of and .

There are two types of vertices in the spherical building , which we called points and lines in Definition 2.2. From now on, we adopt the convention to denote these two types by and , respectively. We let (resp., ) be the set of vertices of type (resp., of type ) in . The natural maps and , associating to each chamber its two boundary vertices, are -equivariant, continuous and surjective (see Reference 23, Prop. 3.5). We denote by and the image in and of the basic open sets .

Definition 5.5.

A marked wall tree in is a simplicial embedding of the model wall tree to such that the limit of when tends to is a vertex of type . We denote by the set of marked wall trees in and endow it with the topology of pointwise convergence.

Note that is locally compact as is locally finite. In fact, it is easy to see how it decomposes into a disjoint union of compact open subspaces. As before, let be the base vertex and define a map

For each we let denote the preimage of under this map. Clearly the subsets are compact open and .

Let us now describe the full automorphism group of the model wall tree. It is a totally disconnected locally compact group with respect to the topology of pointwise convergence. It embeds continuously as a closed subgroup in via the metric realization explained above. In particular, there are canonical projections

that are both continuous homomorphisms. Moreover, is surjective, whereas the image of is isomorphic to the infinite dihedral group. However, we emphasize that the continuous surjection has no section: indeed, no involution that swaps two adjacent vertices in can be lifted to an automorphism of . Let

Since the translation subgroup of is an open subgroup of index , we see that is an open subgroup of index  in . We shall also need to consider the subgroup

Observe that .

For each and , the map belongs to if and only if . Similarly, for each and , the map belongs to if and only if the -action on the spherical building is type-preserving. Recall that is type-preserving; thus the action on is also type-preserving. Thus we get a continuous action of on by precompositions and an action of on by postcompositions. Clearly these actions commute. We endow the quotient spaces and with the quotient topologies. Note that is an -space and is a -space.

Lemma 5.6.

The -action on is proper. Moreover, is a compact -space.

Proof.

The properness is clear from the definitions. The compactness of follows from the fact that has a finite fundamental domain in and the compactness of the spaces .

Let be the set of pairs of opposite vertices with and . This is an open subset of the compact space , hence a locally compact space. We define a map

where represents the vertex at infinity of the ray and similarly for .

Lemma 5.7.

The -action on is proper and free, and the map induces a -equivariant homeomorphism

Proof.

The -action on is free by construction. To see that it is proper it is enough to show that for all , the collection

is a compact subset of , and this is indeed the case, as if , then .

To prove that is bijective, observe that for all , there exists a marked wall tree with . Moreover, for any other marked wall tree , we have if and only if there exists such that . This proves that the map in the lemma is indeed bijective.

Let us now check that the map is continuous. Let be elements of , with . Let and . Then for every , for large enough, is constant on a ball of radius around . If is a point in this ball, it follows that for large enough. Similarly, so that converges to .

We are left to show that is an open map. As in the proof of Lemma 5.4, it suffices by compactness to prove that is open, for every . Indeed, is a union of all , where and are vertices such that belongs to the geodesic segment , and hence open.

Definition 5.8.

We let be the set of pairs , where and is a simplicial isomorphism from to the panel tree . We let be the map given by , where is the common limit of when tends to , and is the class of the geodesic line in . We similarly define and . Observe that the maps and are surjective. We endow and with the quotient topologies obtained under and .

Lemma 5.9.

Fix . Let be the set of simplicial isomorphisms from to , endowed with the topology of pointwise convergence. Then the map defined by is a homeomorphism on its image.

Proof.

Let be such that converges to . Fix a vertex opposite . Let be such that for every , and . Let . Then the map is a parametrization of a geodesic from to which, for large enough, corresponds to . Upon replacing by for some suitable , we can assume that the are chosen so that is eventually constant. Then converges to some with .

Conversely, assume that converges to with and . Let . Then we have for large enough . Since (resp., ) is the projection of (resp., ) to , we immediately get that converges to .

It will be convenient for us to consider various fiber products. If are topological spaces, with continuous maps and , the fiber product is defined as the set . It is equipped with the topology induced from the product topology.

Lemma 5.10.

The map , which associates to the pair , is a homeomorphism, where is endowed with the quotient topology.

Similarly, the map , which associates to the pair , is a homeomorphism.

Proof.

We argue for only, as the other case is similar. The map of the lemma is bijective: every pair of opposite vertices is linked by geodesics forming a tree, and given a pair of opposite vertices, there is an element of realizing a given embedding of the tree, and that element is unique modulo . Since both maps and are continuous, their product is also continuous.

We now have to check that this map is open. Again, by compactness, it suffices to prove that the image of in is an open set. But this set is exactly the set of pairs whose first coordinate is in . Hence it is open.

Lemma 5.11.

The map , which associates to an element with the pair , where is the map obtained by composing with the identification , is continuous.

Proof.

The space is homeomorphic to by Lemma 5.10. The map of the lemma is transported by this homeomorphism to the map , which is continuous.

Proposition 5.12.

Let be an integer, and let be the set of sequences

of vertices which are consecutively opposite and such that is opposite and is opposite . The set is equipped with the topology induced from the product topology. Also let be the set of simplicial isomorphisms of to , with the topology of pointwise convergence.

Then the map

is continuous.

Proof.

We prove the proposition in the special case where and are of type (so that is odd). The other cases are similar. Let be the set of sequences of consecutively opposite vertices, starting from a vertex of type . Note that is naturally identified with the fiber product (with factors).

Let us form the fiber product associated with the map . We then consider the map which associates to the map obtained by composing the map with the perspectivity . Applying Lemma 5.11 (and its symmetric statement with and exchanged) and using the associativity of the fiber product, we see that the map is continuous.

For every isomorphism , we have

Let us now choose an isomorphism that we keep fixed. Given , let us denote by the perspectivity . The map can be factored as the composite of the maps

Since each individual map in that sequence is continuous, the proposition follows.

5.3. The space of restricted marked wall trees

In the next section we will construct measures on the various spaces we consider here. There is a natural measure on that we could construct. However, we will not do it, as this measure fails to satisfy the ergodic properties that we desire. Instead we will consider a certain subspace of , to be denoted , on which the analogous measure will be better behaved. This subsection is devoted to the definition and the study of this subspace and its properties.

For the next definition, recall from Section 5.2 that acts on by precomposition and acts on by postcomposition. Moreover, is a cyclic normal subgroup of acting as integer translations along the line factor of .

Definition 5.13.

Two embeddings are positively equivalent if for every , there exists such that for all . The embeddings and are negatively equivalent if for every , there exists such that for all . We denote the positive and negative equivalences by and , respectively. We denote by the equivalence relation on generated by , and by the orbit equivalence induced by the action of .

Lemma 5.14.

The equivalence relation is -invariant. Moreover, every equivalence class is -invariant, and acts transitively on .

Proof.

By construction, every individual -class is -invariant. Clearly and are invariant under . Moreover, since is a normal subgroup of , the -orbits are permuted by . It follows that is also -invariant. In particular, acts on .

It remains to show that is transitive on . Let . We must find such that . Set for . We choose , which is opposite to both , and , which is opposite to both (see Lemma 2.8). We next successively choose such that:

and ;

and ;

and ;

and .

Thus we have so that . Moreover, . Since is transitive on each fiber of the map by Lemma 5.7, we infer that there exists with . The conclusion follows since .

Fix and . The map induces a map . Let be a sequence of consecutively opposite vertices. We denote by the map obtained by first applying and then the perspectivity .

Lemma 5.15.

Let , and set , and . Then the following assertions are equivalent:

(i)

.

(ii)

There exist an element , an integer , and vertices in such that , the pairs , …, , are all opposite, and .

Proof.

Assume that . By definition, this means that there exists a sequence such that and are equivalent for or or in the same -orbit. Since and are preserved by (see Lemma 5.14) we may assume that , and for , and are either or equivalent. Since and are transitive relations we can assume further that they alternate. Thus (i) implies (ii).

Conversely, let , and let be vertices of such that , and , …, , are all opposite pairs, and such that . Since and all belong to , it follows that must be odd. Set . For all , successively choose satisfying and if is odd, while must satisfy and if is even. Finally, choose with and . By construction we have . It remains to observe that the condition ensures that . Thus (ii) implies (i).

In the next lemma, we use the projection map from Section 5.2.

Lemma 5.16.

Fix an -equivalence class , and let be the stabilizer of so that contains . Fix , and set and . Also let

Then

In particular, the projectivity group is contained in , and is -transitive on .

Proof.

Fix . We have by the definition of . Moreover, recalling that , we have . By Lemma 5.15, there exists an automorphism of of the form for some and some vertices of with and , …, , all opposite pairs such that .

Conversely, let , and let be vertices of such that , the pairs , …, , are all opposite pairs, and define the automorphism . Since is surjective, there exists with . We have by Lemma 5.15.

That is -transitive on follows from Lemma 3.5. Therefore is -transitive on .

We wish to consider a single equivalence class in . A technical issue is that such an equivalence class will not be closed. The obvious solution is to replace the equivalence relation by its closure (as a subset of ). Note that in general the closure of an equivalence relation need not be an equivalence relation. However, the situation is better when a topological group is acting continuously on the ambient space and transitively on the quotient space.

Definition 5.17.

We let be the closure of as a subset of .

Lemma 5.18.

The relation is an equivalence relation and each -equivalence class is closed in . In fact, the -equivalence classes are the closures of the -equivalence classes. In particular, every -equivalence class is -invariant. The quotient space is compact, and the natural -action on is continuous.

Proof.

Recall from Lemma 5.14 that acts transitively on . Therefore, the orbit map induces an equivariant bijection , where is the subgroup of stabilizing some -equivalence class. Let be the closure of in . We have canonical maps

We may now identify with the fiber equivalence relation of the map . Since and , it follows that is a closed subgroup of and that is homeomorphic to . Since is -transitive on by Lemma 5.16, the same holds for , and it follows from Theorem 3.7 that is compact. All the required assertions now follow.

The following crucial definition involves a noncanonical choice.

Definition 5.19.

We fix once and for all an -equivalence class in and denote it by . We call the elements of the restricted marked wall trees. We let be the stabilizer of . In particular, we have .

Lemma 5.20.

The space is closed in and invariant under the action of . The -action on is proper and is a compact -space. The -action on is proper and free, and the restriction of the map to yields -equivariant homeomorphisms and .

Proof.

The first sentence holds by the construction of . The second sentence follows by Lemma 5.20 and Lemma 5.6. To see the third, use Lemma 5.7 and observe that the embedding descends to a continuous map which is injective by the definition of . Moreover, this map is surjective in view of Lemma 5.14. Therefore we have a -equivariant homeomorphism . The last required assertions now follow from Lemma 5.7 and the fact that is a closed normal subgroup of .

Theorem 5.21.

The group is a unimodular group and yields a continuous isomorphism of onto a closed subgroup of acting -transitively on the set of ends . In particular, has a closed cocompact normal subgroup containing such that is compactly generated, topologically simple, and nondiscrete. Furthermore, if is not Bruhat–Tits, then has no nontrivial continuous linear representation over any local field.

Proof.

By Lemma 5.18, the group is the closure of the group , and by Lemma 5.16, the group contains a copy of the projectivity group for some . It follows by Lemma 3.5 that acts -transitively on . As observed before, we have and so that is a closed subgroup of acting -transitively on . The group is described in Theorem 3.7 where its various properties are recorded, as well as the unimodularity of . Since is discrete, we see that is unimodular. We set . We are left to show that the nonlinearity of in case is not Bruhat–Tits. To this end we consider the topologically simple group which is obtained by applying Theorem 3.7 to the closure of the projectivity group . As is profinite and topologically simple, we have since . By Theorem 4.7, the group has no linear representations over local fields. We deduce that shares this property, as the fact that it is topologically simple.

Definition 5.22.

We call the -space the singular Cartan flow.

5.4. The broad picture

In this subsection we pack together the various -spaces previously constructed into the following commutative diagram of -equivariant maps:

In order to keep our notation as light as possible we will not name most of the arrows in diagram (Equation 3), but in what follows we will make clear what they are.

At the beginning of §5.1 we have fixed the model apartment and a positive Weyl chamber emanating from . We defined by

We further defined the map by

where denotes the equivalence class of the section which is a point in , and similarly for which is an opposite point.

At the beginning of §5.2 we fixed the model marked wall tree and a base point . We now relate and . We denote by the unique wall through in such that and fix a simplicial embedding such that is . Recall that . We define the map

Note that the composition agrees with the restriction to of the map (Equation 1) given in §5.2. The maps are clearly -equivariant ( acts on the target space ) and induce corresponding maps . The commutativity of the upper part of diagram (Equation 3) is obvious.

Note that the composed map is -invariant and thus factors through . This explains the map appearing in diagram (Equation 3). We define the map by associating with a pair of chambers the unique pair of elements and such that and are in the boundary of the unique flat that contains both and but disjoint from their closures. By composing we also obtain the map . Note that the composed map is the restriction to of the map (Equation 2) defined in §5.2, namely

Similarly, we can restrict to the maps appearing in Definition 5.8 and obtain maps . The latter, being -invariant, factor through , and we obtain the maps appearing in the diagram. The maps and are the obvious ones, and the maps and are the ones described at the beginning of §5.2. The commutativity of the diagram is clear from the definitions. Finally, the maps are the first and second factor projections.

5.5. Equivariance properties of diagram (Equation 3)

Note that all the maps in diagram (Equation 3) are -equivariant. The following lemmas describe and as spaces of orbits of certain group actions on .

The group contains a subgroup , where is the longest element of , which exchanges the positive and the negative Weyl chamber of . In particular, the map is -equivariant, where acts on by flipping the two coordinates.

Recall our fixed embedding from the previous section. Recall also that acts on by precomposition via its action on .

Now let be the stabilizer of in . Note that is also the stabilizer of , since a maximal flat is uniquely defined by its boundary. Let (resp., ) be the pointwise fixator of (resp., ). By definition, the groups and act on and , so that there is an embedding of the group in and of in .

Proposition 5.23.

Consider the space (resp., ), endowed with the quotient topology and the action of (resp., ). Then:

(i)

The groups , , and are unimodular.

(ii)

The image of (resp., ) in (resp., ) is equal to (resp., ).

(iii)

There is a -equivariant homeomorphism .

(iv)

There is a -equivariant homeomorphism .

Proof.

The image of under the projection is a geodesic in . Note that is exactly the stabilizer of , whereas (resp., ) is the pointwise fixator of (resp., of ).

Since acts -transitively on , it contains an element which flips the two endpoints of . By our choice of , this element acts as on . Furthermore, the two endpoints corresponding to the factor in are fixed by , since . This implies that the image of is exactly . It also follows that the linear part of is equal to . Let . To show that , we first note that contains , so that the stabilizer of in acts transitively on the vertices of . Again using the -transitivity of on , we see that contains an element which acts as a translation of length  on . Hence acts transitively on the set of all lines in which are parallel to . Therefore is transitive on the vertices of so that , since acts sharply transitively on those vertices. Since contains a reflection whose linear part is , it follows that .

To prove that is unimodular, it suffices to prove that is unimodular, since is discrete. But is the stabilizer of in , which contains a translation of . In particular, contains a cocompact lattice, isomorphic to . Therefore it is unimodular. Any open normal subgroup of a unimodular group is also unimodular. Thus and are unimodular.

The map defined (as above) by is clearly -invariant and -equivariant, so it factors through a map , which is -equivariant, and continuous by definition of the quotient topology. The injectivity of is clear. Let us prove its surjectivity. Using Lemma 2.8, we see that for every , contains an element such that . It follows that the image of the map contains every marked flat up to translation. Since contains , it is always possible to translate in order to get back to the origin so that the map is indeed surjective. If , then we see that is a compact open subset of . By compactness, is a homeomorphism on its image, which is , and hence is again open. It follows that is indeed a homeomorphism.

The homeomorphism between and is obtained by composing the map above with the map . This new map clearly factors through . The proof that it is an equivariant homeomorphism is similar as before.

Corollary 5.24.

There exists a closed subgroup and a continuous surjective homomorphism such that the maps and are equivariant with respect to this homomorphism.

Proof.

As above, the image of under the projection is a geodesic line in . We put . By Theorem 5.21, the group is still -transitive on , hence contains an element which flips the two endpoints of . This element acts as on , hence also on .

6. Measuring the topology

In this section, we retain the setting and the notation of the previous one and explain how to construct natural measures on the various topological spaces considered there. In §6.1, we give the construction of visual measures on and use it in §6.2 to construct a Radon measure on . In §6.3, we use the above to construct a Radon measure on . Using the measure on we are able to define a measure on and by this on the various spaces appearing in diagram (Equation 3). That process will be carried out in §6.4.

6.1. The visual measures on

Our goal is to define natural probability measures on , indexed by . We follow the construction of J. Parkinson from Reference 53.

Recall that is the group of simplicial translations of our model apartment and that is the positive Weyl chamber. We denote by the subsemigroup of formed by elements translating to a point in (including possibly points on the walls). This gives a partial order on , defined by if .

Let and be the simple roots associated with the choice of the positive Weyl chamber. In other words, they are the -linear forms on taking integer values on vertices, whose kernel are walls delimiting which are positive on and achieve the value . We also denote by the set of such that and .

Let and be the two generators of such that every is written . We denote .

For and a vertex in , we denote by the set of vertices such that, in an apartment containing and , we have .

There is a natural action of the Weyl group , isomorphic to the symmetric group , on . The group is generated by the two reflections and , which act on by reflections with respect to the walls corresponding to and , respectively.

Lemma 6.1.

Let and be a vertex in . Then the cardinality of does not depend on and we have

for some constant depending on .

Proof.

See Reference 28, Corollary 2.2 or Reference 52, Theorem 5.15.

We will need a more precise calculation. Fix a chamber and a vertex contained in some apartment. Consider the collection of all apartments in containing and . Each element of could be seen as a marked flat, by choosing its unique type preserving identification with taking to and to . For given and we consider in each apartment in the image of the element under the associated identification. We denote by the set of all vertices of obtained this way.

Lemma 6.2.

Denoting , we have

for some constants depending only on . In particular, for every , the quantity tends to as and tend (simultaneously) to .

Proof.

We argue by induction on . The first step of the induction is absorbed by the constants. Let us do the calculation of , the other ones being similar. We refer to Figure 3.

Fix , and let . Let and . We consider the following map : to a point in , we associate the unique point in the intersection of and the convex hull of and . The map is surjective: indeed, if , then and are in some common apartment, and it is possible to find in this apartment such that . We also claim that the restriction of this map to is also injective. Indeed, if , then any apartment containing , and also contains the convex hull of and , and therefore already contains a point . On the other hand, any point such that is contained in some apartment containing , and , and therefore must be equal to . This proves the claim. Hence we have .

Now let , and denote . We still have a surjective map , defined in the same way as the map . However, this map is no longer injective. To count the cardinality of the fibers, choose . This gives a choice of , defined as . There are chambers which have and as their vertices and are not in the convex hull of and . The third vertex of each of these chambers is a possible choice for . Hence .

Definition 6.3.

Let be a vertex in . The visual measure based at , denoted , is the unique measure on such that for all , the set has measure .

The construction of this measure is justified more carefully in Reference 53; it follows from the fact that can be viewed as the projective limit of sets as grows in . We note also that .

Definition 6.4.

Let . The horofunction based at , denoted , is a function defined as follows. Let . Assume that . Then .

This definition does not depend on the particular choice of (see Reference 53, Theorem 3.4). The horofunction satisfies the following cocycle relation Reference 53, Proposition 3.5.

Lemma 6.5.

For all and , we have .

Proposition 6.6.

For vertices in , the measures and are absolutely continuous relative to each other. Furthermore, for all , we have

Proof.

See Reference 53, Theorem 3.17.

Definition 6.7.

We denote by the measure class of .

Proposition 6.8.

The set is of conull measure (relative to the measure class ).

Proof.

For every vertex , let (resp., ) be the subset of composed of pairs of chambers which are in the boundary of an apartment containing (resp., and are opposite).

Then . By countability it is sufficient to prove that for every we have , for a fixed vertex . Since and are in the same measure class, it is sufficient to prove that for every vertex .

By Fubini, it is enough to prove that for almost every chamber at infinity , the set of chambers such that is of full measure (in the set of chambers in the same apartment as and ). Let be the restriction of the measure to the set of those chambers with . We have to prove that .

Recall the sets discussed in Lemma 6.2 and set . It is clear that . We claim that this inclusion is actually an equality. Indeed, if , then every finite subset of is contained in some apartment. Hence by Theorem 2.3 is also contained in an apartment, and then it is clear that and are opposite in it.

Note that the intersection is decreasing in the sense that for every such that , we have . Hence it is enough to prove that tends to when . Equivalently, we need to show that for every , the limit of is as tends to infinity (simultaneously in both directions). This follows from Lemma 6.2, as .

6.2. The Radon measure on

In this section we construct a natural Radon measure on , which is invariant by the actions of . The existence of such a measure is well known to experts (see for example Reference 51 for a possible definition); its construction is nevertheless usually different than what we propose here.

Lemma 6.9.

For and a vertex in , the quantity

with a point in the apartment containing and , does not depend on .

Furthermore, for every vertex , we have

Proof.

Let us prove first that is independent of . Let and be two points in the apartment containing and . Using the assumption that and are opposite, we have that .

Hence by Lemma 6.5 we have

Now let us turn to the second equality. Fix . Then, using Lemma 6.5 again, we have

For a fixed vertex in we define the measure on by the formula

By Lemma 6.9 and Proposition 6.6, and also using the fact that for every , we have

Thus the measure is independent on the choice of . We get that this measure is -invariant, as for all we have and ; hence .

Using Proposition 6.8 we view as a measure on which, in view of its independence on , we denote . Thus is a -invariant measure on .

Recall that for a vertex we define to be the space simplicial embeddings satisfying and let be the image of under the projection . Note that is injective in restriction to , thus induces a homeomorphism by Lemma 5.4.

Lemma 6.10.

We have .

Proof.

By definition, .

By Lemma 6.9, if , we have . Hence .

Corollary 6.11.

The measure is a -invariant Radon measure on the locally compact space which is in the measure class of .

Proof.

The only thing that does not immediately follow from the discussion above is the fact that is finite on compact sets. This follows from Lemma 6.10, as is an open cover of .

6.3. The Radon measure on

The first part of this section is devoted to the construction of a Radon measure on ; see Definition 6.14 and Lemma 6.15 below. The construction is similar to the construction of given in the previous section. The second part of this section is a preparation for the proof that the measures and are compatible which will be given in the next section; see Theorem 6.21.

For (resp., ), we define the horofunction (resp., ) by , for any chamber adjacent to (resp.,